Victims and Offenders, 4:197–213, 2009
Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 1556-4886 print/1556-4991 online
DOI: 10.1080/15564880802612631
Eight Lessons from Moneyball:
The High Cost of Ignoring
Evidence-Based Corrections
1556-4991
1556-4886
UVAO
Victims
and Offenders
Offenders, Vol. 4, No. 1, December 2008: pp. 1–26
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
Moneyball
Francis T. Cullen, Andrew J. Myer, and Edward J. Latessa
Division of Criminal Justice, University of Cincinnati, Cincinnati, Ohio, USA
Abstract: Michael Lewis’s book, Moneyball, documents the effective use of evidencebased practices by Billy Beane, the general manager of the Oakland Athletics. Lewis
shows how Beane’s reliance on theoretically relevant statistics and on a scientific
approach to baseball allowed him to achieve winning seasons despite being burdened
by severe budget constraints. His approach spurred much antagonism in the baseball
community because it challenged many long-standing, but ultimately unsupported,
practices. In this context, Moneyball provides a useful conduit through which to assess
why many correctional agencies are ineffective in the services they provide. In fact, the
points of comparison between baseball and correctional practices are striking and warrant careful illumination. Toward this end, we specify eight lessons that corrections
can learn from Moneyball and evidence-based baseball.
Keywords: evidence-based intervention, corrections, rehabilitation
Over the past two decades, there has been an increasing call to base decisions
in a variety of fields on empirical evidence (Ayres, 2007). Underlying this call
is the claim that practices in many domains are not based on carefully
collected and weighed data but on clinical expertise at best and on “gut feelings,”
intuition, custom, and ideology at worst. As Ayres (2007) points out in his
recent book, Super Crunchers, the cost of ignoring the “numbers” is less than
optimal decision making. In human terms, this means that medical patients
needlessly die, challenged children do not learn to read well, investors in the
stock market go bankrupt, the mentally ill are not cured, and offenders are
not reformed and victimize again.
For a half century, research has shown repeatedly that actuarial decision
making outperforms clinical judgments (Ayres, 2007). Still, during this period,
statistical evidence often did not guide interventions into people’s lives,
Address correspondence to Francis T. Cullen, Division of Criminal Justice, PO Box
210389, University of Cincinnati, Cincinnati, OH 45221. E-mail: cullenft@email.uc.edu
197
198
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
including within medicine. However, a key turning point in the movement to
use empirical data to inform practice came from a 1992 article, authored by a
working group headed by Gordon Guyatt, called “Evidence-Based Medicine”
(Ayres, 2007). In this widely read essay, Guyatt and his colleagues persuasively argued for a paradigm shift. Traditionally, physicians would receive
medical training in the “basic mechanisms of disease and patho-physiologic
principles.” Then, through “unsystematic observations from clinical experience”
and a dose of common sense, they would develop the expertise to “evaluate
new tests and treatments” and to diagnose and intervene with patients (1992,
p. 2421). The “new paradigm,” however, would not discount clinical experience
but would supplement it by equipping doctors with the motivation and skills
needed to consult the extant research literature when making diagnoses and
delivering treatment. “The final assumption of the new paradigm,” Guyatt
et al. (1992, p. 2421) noted, “is that physicians whose practice is based on an
understanding of the underlying evidence will provide superior patient care”
(see also Sackett & Rosenberg, 1995; Timmerman & Berg, 2003).
This article was an exposé of sorts, because it questioned the assumption
that current medical practice was informed by the most rigorous scientific
findings available. Quasi-scientific practices inspire notions of quackery and
yield potentially disquieting consequences. Indeed, it is estimated that from
40,000 to 100,000 hospital patients die each year from medical errors, “a rate
higher than deaths attributed to highway accidents, AIDS or breast cancer”
(Wolf, 2000, p. 251). These errors have diverse sources, but a chief cause is the
failure of hospitals to incorporate evidence-based practices into their daily
operations (Berwick, Calkins, McCannon, & Hackbarth, 2006; Wolf, 2000). As
Rothman (2007, p. 54) notes, “there is no minimizing the amount of outright
medical incompetence. . . . When a majority of patients are not receiving
standard care for standard conditions, evidence-based medicine has much to
commend it.”
Medicine is a high-status field and thus offers an exemplar for others
involved in the care and treatment of humans. Not surprisingly perhaps,
scholars in other disciplines have embraced the logic of this new medical paradigm to call for evidence-based approaches in their fields of inquiry and practice. Thus, to name but a few, authors have advocated evidence-based
education (Davies, 1999), management (Pfeffer & Sutton, 2006), public health
(Rychetnik, Hawe, Waters, Barratt, & Frommer, 2004), social work (Gilgun,
2005), and health and human services (Roberts & Yeager, 2004). Criminal justice has not been immune to this movement. Sherman (1998) quickly saw the
wisdom of this approach and set forth a case for evidence-based policing; other
scholars have made a similar case for crime prevention (Welsh & Farrington,
2006) and corrections (Cullen & Gendreau, 2000; MacKenzie, 2001, 2006).
The premise that evidence matters received another significant boost from
a very unlikely source, Michael Lewis’s (2003) best seller Moneyball: The Art
Moneyball
of Winning an Unfair Game. Lewis was puzzled by an odd empirical fact.
Despite being in a small market and having a shoestring budget, the Oakland
Athletics baseball team regularly won over 90 games a year and frequently
appeared in the playoffs. How was this possible? By contrast, the New York
Yankees outspent the Athletics—or “A’s” as they are known—by several
times. It is not that the size of the payroll does not matter. The Yankees also
won many games and, in fact, research shows that money spent on players’
salaries is related to winning (Hall, Szymanski, & Zimbalist, 2002; Wiseman
& Chatterjee, 2003). Still, whereas the disparity in the Yankees’ and Athletics’
payrolls was large, the disparity in wins was not. What were the A’s doing to
surmount the huge competitive disadvantage they faced with the Yankees and
other financially flush teams?
Lewis’s answer was that the Oakland A’s were practicing evidence-based
management. Decisions on which players to draft, play, retain, and trade were
being made on the basis of statistics rather than on “clinical” experience from
years of simply “being in baseball.” This approach was the brainchild of the
Athletics’ general manager, Billy Beane, and was portrayed vividly in Lewis’s
Moneyball. The book seemed to strike a chord, earning wonderful reviews
(see, e.g., Thaler & Sunstein, 2003) and its way onto the best-seller list.
In this context, we suggest that Moneyball is a useful conduit for understanding the need to use evidence-based practices within the field of corrections.
At first glance, baseball and corrections might appear to have little in
common. But they share the common plight of being social domains in which
irrational practices, based on unsystematic observation and “common sense,”
have been enshrined with legitimacy. Both domains also are at the precipice
of embracing a new paradigm—of leaping into the realm where decisions are
guided by evidence. More specifically, Moneyball is a concrete way to illuminate how the correctional enterprise might be improved. We derive and share
eight lessons from its pages. First, however, we will briefly tell the unlikely
story of Billy Beane and the Oakland A’s.
MONEYBALL
The Traditional Baseball Paradigm
“When you get right down to it,” observes Schwarz (2004, p. xiii), “no corner
of American culture is more precisely counted, more passionately quantified,
than the performance of baseball players.” This fascination with numbers is
not new. In fact, notes Schwarz, “arguments over the relative merits of batting
average and fielding percentage, runs scored and runs driven in, date back to
the game’s earliest days in the nineteenth century” (pp. xii–xiv). Ironically,
despite the existence of an unending flow of data, baseball officials have long
resisted attempts to use statistical evidence to guide their decisions. They are
199
200
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
particularly suspicious of outsiders who have never played, coached, or otherwise worked in baseball—that is, who have never been “within the white
lines” of major league baseball (Gray, 2006, p. 195). Instead, they place a premium on what Merton (1972) calls “insider knowledge”—expertise derived
from first-hand experiences that is not available to those not in the group.
Clinical knowledge, in short, trumps actuarial knowledge.
The traditional baseball paradigm is based on four beliefs. First, a player’s
talent is most accurately appraised by having “baseball men”—scouts—look at
the individual in person. From years of playing and watching the game, it is
believed that scouts have the judgment to distinguish which prospects have
major league potential and should be drafted. Second, the statistics that have
long been collected—batting average, runs batted in, earned run average—are
more than adequate to assess a player’s performance and value to a team.
Third, in game situations, decisions should be made according the “The
Book”—an unwritten compilation of baseball wisdom learned from insider
experiences. This might involve, for example, batting a speedy player first in
the lineup or bunting to move a runner into scoring position. Whether these
customs—these “received truths”—stand up to empirical scrutiny is of no concern. Fourth, beyond “The Book,” intuition—presumably based on an acute
reading of unique game situations—is a legitimate basis for managerial decisions. Quirky decisions that win games are to be celebrated as instances of
baseball genius. Quirky decisions that lose games are to be seen as bold moves
that just did not work out. The possibility that selective attention to success
over failure might produce biased, ineffective future decision making is not a
consideration.
The New Paradigm: Evidence-Based Baseball
As Gray (2006, p. 90) notes, “society’s anti-science impulses are mirrored
in the insider baseball culture.” Over the years, baseball was depicted as being
guided by wise traditions and by clinical expertise derived from years of experience in dealing with the unique situations and irreducible complexities
inherent in the game of baseball. This near-hegemonic worldview, however,
has been challenged during the past three decades. A new paradigm has
emerged, one that embraces science, an actuarial approach, and an evidencebased analysis of baseball’s traditional wisdoms. The major figure within this
paradigm has been Bill James. An iconoclastic figure from the nation’s heartland in Kansas, James produced reams of data and poignant essays that questioned widely accepted baseball knowledge and practices (Gray, 2006).
James was not the first to use evidence to provide new visions of the baseball enterprise. Branch Rickey, who is best known for helping to break the
major league color barrier by bringing Jackie Robinson to the Brooklyn Dodgers, hired Alan Roth in 1947 to provide detailed statistical analyses of his
Moneyball
players. With a law degree from the University of Michigan, Rickey was receptive to data that would give him an edge in player decisions. In fact, “many of
Rickey’s decisions later hailed as brilliant . . . were bolstered by Roth’s information” (Schwarz, 2004, p. 57).
Over the years, however, the use of evidence to inform baseball decisions
proved sporadic and overwhelmed by the traditional insider paradigm. Starting
in the late 1970s, Bill James would alter the intellectual landscape of professional baseball. Working in relative obscurity at first, James would become
nationally known and, eventually, would be employed as an advisor to the
Boston Red Sox (Gray, 2006). Three considerations contributed to his status
and influence.
First, he gave the new paradigm a name: “sabermetrics.” James derived
this term “for his science” by marrying “the acronym for the Society for American
Baseball Research and the Latin Suffix for measurement” (Schwarz, 2004,
p. 127). This construct was important because it allowed other baseball
researchers to join an identifiable movement; they would now be known as
“sabermetricians.”
Second, James engaged in what Hagan (1973) calls the “sociology of the
interesting.” His strategy was to take cherished folk wisdoms and then to
show that, in fact, they are incorrect. For a generation of baseball fans raised
in the 1960s and 1970s, this irreverence toward authority—this ability to
unmask supposed truths as falsehoods—was fun if not exhilarating. Baseball’s
power elite thus were portrayed as stodgy and stupid, as clinging to outdated
practices just as had the medical quacks of the 1600s.
Third and most important, James provided rigorous data to substantiate his
claims. His first publication was called the 1977 Baseball Abstract: Featuring
18 Categories of Statistical Information That You Just Cannot Find Anywhere
Else (Gray, 2006, p. 31). It sold for $3.50. Subsequent editions of the Baseball
Abstract appeared and then other books followed. Again, the appeal of James’s
analyses was that his science revealed that the traditional paradigm simply misunderstood the nature of baseball and thus led to irrational practices. For example, James questioned the wisdom of attempted stolen bases and sacrifice bunts
because they exchanged a base gained for a potential out; he showed that
on-base-percentage (OBP), which included walks as well as hits, was a better
predictor of runs scored than batting average; he revealed how players’ batting
averages could be affected by the dimensions of ball parks; and he questioned
whether there was much evidence that “clutch” hitting exists or that the order in
which players bat is a strong predictor of runs scored (Gray, 2006).
James certainly has a wide following outside baseball. Importantly, a new
generation of mostly college-educated general managers is also increasingly
receptive to sabermetrics. In 2002, the Red Sox legitimated Bill James when
they hired him as a consultant. Two years later, the team broke the “curse of the
Babe” and won their first World Series since trading Babe Ruth to the Yankees
201
202
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
in 1919. In 2007, another championship came to the Red Sox. James certainly
was not the architect of the team, but his insights were a factor in the players
signed, retained, and traded by the Red Sox. As Gray (2006, p. 156) observes,
“Bill’s influence on Major League Baseball is analogous to Charles Darwin’s
influence on nature. By changing the way we understand it, and changing the
terms of the discussion about it, he did much to change the thing itself.”
Still, within the baseball community, receptivity to his paradigm remains
ambivalent and often outright hostile. A vigorous clash of paradigms persists.
Insider knowledge continues to be trumpeted. Thus, in a recent column on
Dusty Baker, the Cincinnati Reds’ new manager, Paul Daugherty (2008,
p. C1) observed that “if Baker manages by a book, it’s one inside his head, not
one written by Bill James.” After all, Baker has years of experience on which
to draw. As Daugherty concluded, “Here’s a stat: Wins as manager: Dusty
Baker, 1,162; Bill James, 0” (p. C10). Of course, the counterfactual is not considered: How many games might Baker have won had he made evidencebased decisions? But this is not the issue; James is not an insider, so what
does he really know?
Billy Beane and the Oakland Athletics
In 1980, Billy Beane forfeited a football and baseball scholarship to Stanford
University to sign with the New York Mets. Along with Darrell Strawberry,
he had been one of two players the Mets had selected in the first round of the
major league draft. Beane had inordinate athletic talent and the “look” of an
exceptional physical specimen. A decade later, however, he sported a dismal
.219 batting average and felt it was wiser to halt his career and become a
scout for the Oakland A’s.
By 1997, he had ascended to the position of the team’s general manager.
In so doing, he was prepared to conduct an experiment in sabermetrics—a
real-life test of Bill James’s new paradigm. What would happen if the team’s
decisions were based on scientific data?
This experiment was prompted by four factors. First, ironically, his own
personal “insider” experience in baseball revealed how wrong insider knowledge could be. He looked like the prototypical outfielder and wowed the scouts
with his sheer athleticism. But, as Beane understood, the hidden reality was
that he could not hit very well. Second, when he joined the Athletics, the general manager was Sandy Alderson, a Harvard law school graduate who had
never played baseball but who was an advocate of Bill James. He provided
Beane with access to the sabermetrics’ paradigm. Third, not wed to the traditional insider paradigm, Beane became enamored with the possibilities that
inhered in actuarial decision making. It might give him an edge when competing
against other teams. Fourth, the Oakland A’s were financially strapped. With
a limited budget, Beane would have to win without the luxury of high-priced
Moneyball
players. Unless he drafted well and traded for bargains, his team would be
consigned to the lower echelon of the American League.
Beane’s success in using evidence-based baseball is wonderfully chronicled in Michael Lewis’s Moneyball. Dismantling the Athletics’ reigning organizational culture that reflected the traditional insider paradigm, he insisted on
making player personnel decisions based on meaningful statistics that could
be shown to predict success in the major leagues (such as on-base-percentage).
In so doing, he compiled a team that enjoyed a high level of success. As Table 1
shows, within two years the A’s had a winning record. Then, from 2000 until
2006, the team averaged nearly 95 wins a year. Over the same period, the
powerful New York Yankees averaged only two wins more.
The success of the A’s is particularly noteworthy because of the limited budget available to them. As can be seen in Table 2, from 1997 to 2005 the A’s were a
true bargain: they ranked first among major league teams in the dollars spent per
win ($423,053). By contrast, the success of the Yankees was fueled by a payment
that was almost three times higher ($1,221,173 per win). In the next two years
(data not shown), the A’s dipped to fourth in the league in cost per win, mainly
due to a poor 2007 season. Still, the point remain: during much of the last decade,
the Oakland Athletics were highly successful despite a dismal budget.
This accomplishment is even more remarkable when one realizes that the
A’s achieved their consistent high level of winning despite having to
“unload”—through trades or free agency—a cavalcade of all-star players that
the team could not afford to keep. Faced with the inability to pay its proven
stars, the A’s lost players such as Johnny Damon, Jermaine Dye, Ray
Durham, Keith Foulke, Jason Giambi, Dan Haren, Tim Hudson, Jason Isringhausen, Billy Koch, Mark McGuire, Mark Mulder, Nick Swisher, Miguel
Tejada, and Barry Zito. How successful might the A’s have been if Beane had
been able to use his evidence-based management style unconstrained by budgetary considerations?
Table 1: Comparative records for the Oakland Athletics
and New York Yankees, 1997–2007 (wins reported).
Year
Oakland Athletics
New York Yankees
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
65
74
87
91
102
103
96
91
88
93
76
96
114
96
87
95
103
101
101
95
97
94
203
204
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
Table 2: The cost of wins for major league baseball teams, 1997–2005.
Team
Oakland Athletics
Minnesota Twins
Washington Nationals
Pittsburg Pirates
Florida Marlins
Kansas City Royals
Milwaukee Brewers
Tampa Bay Devil Rays
Cincinnati Reds
San Diego Padres
Chicago White Sox
Houston Astros
Detroit Tigers
Toronto Blue Jays
San Francisco Giants
Philadelphia Phillies
Cleveland Indians
Los Angeles Angels
St. Louis Cardinals
Colorado Rockies
Seattle Mariners
Chicago Cubs
Baltimore Orioles
Arizona Diamondbacks
Texas Rangers
Atlanta Braves
Los Angeles Dodgers
New York Mets
Boston Red Sox
New York Yankees
Rank Order in
Cost Per Win
Mean Cost Per
Win in Dollars
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
423,053
439,174
443,448
464,791
492,227
515,703
524,978
574,833
598,161
604,784
604,998
659,983
676,336
678,538
702,021
714,701
728,524
732,408
767,009
770,079
787,687
862,166
899,322
889,973
930,985
960,637
969,097
998,087
1,005,667
1,221,173
In the end, evidence-based baseball assumes that carefully analyzed evidence can minimize the biases and inefficiencies that inhere in decisions based
on personal, unsystematic observations of one’s individual experiences. Billy
Beane’s experiment provides an exemplar of science’s power to increase the odds
of success. Not all have been blind to this fact; Moneyball thinking has emerged
as a viable paradigm that has its adherents. Even so, the resistance to scientific
baseball has been stiff. In an epilogue to a later edition of Moneyball, Lewis
described the debate as a “religious war.” Echoing this view, Leonhardt (2005,
p. 4–1) observes that the book has inspired “the equivalent of a theological dispute over whether baseball is a game of mystery or of data, of statistics and analysis or of intuition and human instinct.” This reluctance to consider the benefits
of evidence is perhaps expectable. Much is being challenged—an ideology, a way
of life, a sense of being authoritative. Nonetheless, the point of these commentaries is that the continued embrace of the traditional baseball paradigm has been
more a defense of the sacred than rooted in persuasive argument—almost the
parallel of the Scopes trial in which evolution was rejected less on its own merits
and more for the broader threat it posed to all that made life meaningful.
Moneyball
EIGHT LESSONS
As Ayres (2007, p. 150) notes, “there is an iron-clad law that it’s easier for
people to warm up to applications of Super Crunching outside of their own
area of expertise. It’s devilishly hard for traditional, non-empirical evaluators to even consider the possibility that quantified predictions might do a
better than job than they can do on their own home turf.” It is for this very
reason that we have turned to baseball to send the broader message of the
importance of embracing an evidence-based approach in our own realm of
corrections. In fact, baseball and corrections have much in common. Eight
lessons, we argue, can be learned from Moneyball about the correctional
enterprise.
Lesson #1: Correctional Treatment Programs are the Oakland A’s
of Corrections
When the New York Yankees incorrectly judge a player’s talent, it is a disappointment but not a tragedy. With a salary budget in excess of $200 million,
the owner simply opens up his wallet and purchases the next star free agent.
Billy Beane’s Oakland Athletics are not so fortunate. With limited resources
at hand, there are few second chances to “get it right.” Beane must constantly
make potentially risky player trades, giving up rising stars for the next set of
unproven prospects. Without evidence-based decisions, the consequences
could easily be years of dismal failure.
Corrections and, in particular, offender treatment programs are the
Oakland A’s of governmental services. With offender populations under supervision rising to historic levels and state budget deficits looming large, corrections is woefully underfinanced. In this challenging environment, scarce
resources must be used judiciously. There is simply no room to experiment
with interventions that have not been proven to be effective. With high risk
offenders, moreover, there are few second chances. If evidence-based treatment is not delivered, the likelihood that they will recidivate—victimizing
people and property many times over—is inordinately high.
Lesson #2: Like Baseball, Corrections is Often Based on
“Common Sense,” Custom, and Imitation—Rather
than on Scientific Evidence
Baseball’s traditional insider paradigm has its cousin within corrections.
Across the years, too few offender treatment programs have been based on
empirically supported intervention strategies. Academic experts have been
absent—either because they had no knowledge to share or because they were
seen as outsiders. Programs, especially “innovative” interventions, instead
were based on common sense and then often imitated across agencies and
205
206
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
states (Gendreau, Goggin, Cullen, & Paparozzi, 2002). Instances of such
“correctional quackery” are too numerous to list, but some recent examples
include scared straight programs, intensive supervision, and having offenders
sing in choirs, raise pets, engage in long-distance running, and cross-dress to
“get in touch with their feminine side” (Latessa, Cullen, & Gendreau, 2002;
see also MacKenzie, 2001, 2006). How these programs would change the
known risk factors for recidivism remains a mystery.
Lesson #3: Like Baseball, in Corrections “Looks” are
More Important than Effectiveness
In Moneyball, there is a wonderful section in which scouts, discussing
draft prospects, trumpet those who “look like a stud” and have a “face with
character.” Players who deviated from this image of the prototypical athlete—
a bit small, a large rear end, pudgy rather than chiseled, an arm that seemed
to throw a touch too slow—were relegated to the scout’s dustbin. In dismay,
Billy Beane would then consult the statistics and show why “looks” were unrelated to past and thus future performance. Muscles and a square jaw simply
mattered much less than on-base and slugging percentages. Beane would thus
discount the scouts’ insider views and draft by actuarial performance—by the
evidence. The result is that he succeeded in drafting wisely, selecting players
that other teams foolishly overlooked.
Correctional officials—or the politicians who guide their efforts—also
readily embrace programs that “look good.” Among the most egregious examples are correctional boot camps. These programs were implemented largely
because military discipline is accorded a privileged place in our national consciousness. It is seen as having “broken down” and “built back up” the character of many immature, if not wayward, young men. Having personally
experienced the military, many elected and correctional officials were easily
persuaded that the tough love of boot camps would instill moral fiber within
juveniles and younger adults. What officials did not do, however, was to consult any evidence on whether military experience successfully reformed
criminals and whether the sources of recidivism would be changed through
the rigors of boot camp life. Of course, what “looked good” proved to be a
failed experiment (Cullen, Blevins, Trager, & Gendreau, 2005; MacKenzie,
2006).
Lesson #4: Like Baseball, in Corrections the Wrong Theory
Can Lead to Stupid Decisions
Based on Bill James’s analysis, Beane embraced a “theory of baseball”
that contravened “The Book” at the heart of the insider’s paradigm. Beyond
pitching, the key to winning games is to score runs within the context of an
inning bounded by three outs. This simple conceptual insight, however, has
Moneyball
potentially profound implications. Within any given game, it makes problematic the sacrifice bunt (an out is exchanged for a base) and the attempted steal
(where the risk of an out is present). This is because, in terms of producing
runs scored, the cost of an out usually exceeds the benefits of advancing a runner one base. This insight also might affect who a team should draft. When
high batting averages are privileged, players who secure walks are often overlooked. But on-base-percentage, which as noted includes walks, is a better
predictor of runs scored than mere batting average. The theory of baseball
explains why: a base is gained without the cost of an out.
Within corrections, theories detached from empirical evidence abound and
lead to hopelessly flawed interventions. On occasion, these theories are kindhearted, such as when the goal is to boost offenders’ self-esteem in the mistaken
belief that poor self-confidence underlies wayward conduct (Andrews & Bonta,
2006). Too often, the theories embrace a crude rational choice perspective in
which it is asserted that some form of threat, harsh discipline, or pain will
teach that crime does not pay and straighten out offenders. These impoverished
theories, which conveniently neglect the empirical literature on predictors of
recidivism, have little chance of working (Cullen, Pratt, Micelli, & Moon, 2002;
see also Gendreau, Little, & Goggin, 1996). Understanding the cause of the
problem—an understanding rooted in empirical data—is a prerequisite for its
solution.
Lesson #5: Like Baseball, in Corrections Actuarial Data Lead to
More Accurate Decisions than Personal Experience and “Gut
Level” Decisions
In Moneyball, Billy Beane is depicted on draft day as celebrating the
apparent stupidity of the franchises selecting players ahead of the Oakland
A’s. A common mistake is when teams draft “can’t miss” high school pitchers.
In fact, these pitchers are prone to injury and have compiled limited statistical
profiles against mostly untalented hitters. By contrast, Beane’s top pitching
selections—those that are awarded lucrative contracts—are virtually all hurlers who played in college and have proven their durability and talent over a
longer stretch of time. Their statistics, in short, predict future performance.
Similar to baseball, corrections is a field replete with decisions: who to
incarcerate, who to parole, who to allocate services, and so on. In an amazing
display of blindness or arrogance, those making these decisions—many of
whom have never had a criminology course, let alone have read the relevant
empirical literature—do so without any inkling that their choices may be governed by false criteria (e.g., whether a lawbreaker displays remorse at a hearing).
This is especially true when judging an offender’s risk of recidivating. To be
sure, predicting the future—whether it is the performance of a baseball player
or an offender—is a daunting challenge. Errors will be made. But the reality is
207
208
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
that corrections now has available offender assessment instruments that
increase the odds of successfully prognosticating behavior (Andrews & Bonta,
2006; Bonta, 1996). Failure to engage in evidence-based decision making thus
borders on the irresponsible. In baseball, the consequence is a failed draft; in
corrections, an offender is needlessly confined or dangerously released.
Lesson #6: Like Baseball, in Corrections Knowledge
Destruction Techniques will be Used to Reject
Evidence-Based Approaches
Billy Beane was not a crusader for evidence-based baseball. In fact, he
was content to remain in obscurity, using evidence to quietly exploit the inefficiencies of his competitors. Michael Lewis’s Moneyball, however, unmasked
and nationally publicized Beane’s strategies. In many quarters where the traditional insider paradigm prevails, efforts were quickly made to undermine
his approach. Some attacks were personal, depicting Beane as egotistical for
thinking he was a so-called genius. Other claims were more subtle, trying to
tarnish his accomplishments by noting that his team had not made it to the
World Series. He also was accused of winning due to plain dumb luck—of fortuitously drafting three pitchers who carried his team (Tim Hudson, Mark
Mulder, and Barry Zito). These critiques, of course, never address two more
fundamental questions: Why would the evidence Beane uses not lead to better
decision making? And how successful would the Oakland A’s be if the low-budget team, which cannot retain its stars, made decisions on intuition rather
than on hard data?
In corrections, these attempts to undermine the accomplishments of successful interventions are known as “knowledge destruction techniques”
(Andrews & Bonta, 2006; see also Gottfredson, 1979). Favored “insider” interventions are defended without a shred of evidence. Successful “outsider” interventions are then held to impossible standards of proof (e.g., the follow-up
period was only two years, not three years; meta-analyses do not include
many unpublished studies). Of course, skepticism is a healthy norm within
the scientific community. But differential standards of “proof”—virtually none
for practices favored by insiders and the gold standard for evidence-based
programs—are the hallmark of knowledge destruction.
Lesson #7: Like Baseball, in Corrections There is a High Cost
to Ignoring the Scientific Evidence on What Works
In the deciding seventh game of the 2003 American League Series, the
Red Sox led the Yankees 5 to 2 in the eighth inning. Pedro Martinez had
pitched a remarkable game. The Sox’s manager, Grady Little, had to decide
whether to keep Martinez in the game or to replace him with a fresh reliever.
Moneyball
Little went with his “gut” and decided to “win or lose with Pedro.” This decision
might not have been controversial except for the fact that Little had been
given statistics showing that, across the season, Martinez’s performance
declined substantially after the seventh inning and after he had thrown
105 pitches. Starting on pitch 110 to Derek Jeter, the Yankees hit a double,
single, double, and double—tying the game at 5 apiece. The Red Sox would lose
the game—and the team’s chance to play in the World Series—in extra
innings. Grady Little would be fired as the Red Sox’s manager (Schwarz, 2004).
Like baseball, corrections is not immune to the high cost of ignoring the
evidence (Van Voorhis, 1987). It is especially insidious, however, that many of
these untoward consequences are hidden from public view. When elected officials trumpet a new “get tough” correctional practice based on pure speculation,
they often are acclaimed for “doing something” about crime. Boot camps,
again, comprise a priceless example, because they brought officials much fanfare and exploited the cultural beliefs of the public that military discipline
builds moral fiber (Cullen et al., 2005). But the eventual costs—typically
never disclosed to the public—were inordinate. Thus, millions of dollars were
wasted on an intervention that had scant prospects of working; many young
offenders were not diverted from a dismal life in crime; and many community
members were needlessly victimized by offenders who might well have been
reformed by evidence-based interventions. Unfortunately, accountability is
limited. Unlike in baseball where Grady Little was fired for ignoring the data,
the purveyors of correctional quackery are rarely asked to justify their failures.
The time may well have come to do so.
Lesson #8: Like Baseball, in Corrections Evidence-Based
Practices will Eventually be Difficult to Ignore
The new baseball paradigm advanced by Bill James and brought to life
vividly in Moneyball is not going to disappear. Some baseball franchises will
continue to ignore evidence to their peril; others will use the paradigm intermittently; and still others—a minority for now—will see evidence as integral
to their enterprise. In the end, evidence-based baseball might well function
like evolutionary theory. Because no experimental design study can be conducted and outcomes are open to different interpretations, the theory cannot
be definitively proven. True believers in the traditional paradigm thus will have
room to cling to old truths. But the evidence in favor of evidence-based baseball
will mount over the years—just as the fossil finds have for evolution—to the
point where only those of the traditional faith will deny its importance.
In corrections, a similar struggle will be faced. With so much at stake—
offender reform, community safety, public monies foolishly wasted—the malpractice of ignoring evidence-based interventions will be harder to defend. The
equivalent of a Correctional Moneyball certainly would help the cause! But in
209
210
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
its absence, scholars are creating an increasing body of evidence outlining the
components or principles of effective and ineffective interventions (see, e.g.,
Andrews & Bonta, 2006; Gendreau, 1996; Gendreau, Smith, & French, 2006;
Lipsey & Cullen, 2007; MacKenzie, 2006; Palmer, 2002). This knowledge base
creates the ability to ask correctional officials and agencies a powerful question:
Why aren’t you doing what works?
CONCLUSION
Evidence-based approaches—whether in baseball or medicine or corrections—
are accused of taking the art and humanity out of a field’s enterprise (Gray,
2006; Rothman, 2007). And it must be admitted that an extreme actuarial
approach that denies the wisdom of clinical experience is unwarranted. But
the reality is that we do not live in a world populated by a bunch of “Houses”—
the memorable doctor on the television series whose amazing clinical intuition
allows him to diagnose seemingly mystifying medical conditions. In most contexts, the problem is not that we risk snuffing out such creativity and insider
acuity. Rather, the greater risk is that we will subject people to practices that
we have not bothered to show empirically do more good than harm.
Within corrections, however, special challenges remain. It is not sufficient
to smugly criticize the purveyors of boot camps and similar misguided interventions as correctional quacks. For an evidence-based paradigm to take hold
and shape practice, three important challenges will have to be confronted
(Cullen & Gendreau, 2000).
First, as a profession, criminologists are most comfortable conducting
studies showing how highly touted practices in corrections are, in fact, ineffective (Cullen & Gendreau, 2001). Although invaluable, these efforts do not
address the reverse side of the coin: If certain programs have few effects, then
what does work to reduce recidivism? Again, strides in this direction have
been taken, but mostly by a limited and aging group of scholars (Cullen,
2005). The challenge ahead is thus for a new generation of criminologists to
engage in knowledge construction—that is, to use evidence to design the interventions capable of reforming offenders.
Second, as information on what works continues to mount—as it is now
doing—knowledge dissemination will have to occur. Sometimes called “technology transfer,” in corrections there are minimal conduits for sharing
detailed knowledge on how best to assess and reform offenders. In many
cases, the difficulty is not practitioners’ receptivity to knowledge but their
inability to secure training in evidence-based practices. There is no functional
equivalent in corrections to medical schools, but similar training facilities will
be needed.
Third, knowledge fidelity will be a continuing concern. Even when evidencebased practices are developed and shared, it will be difficult to ensure that
Moneyball
programs are implemented and sustained with integrity. Limited resources, an
absence of follow-up training, shifting staff, a changing political environment—
these and a range of other factors can result in corners being cut and treatments being robbed of their capacity to transform the wayward. This problem
is not unique to corrections; it occurs in medicine as well. But it must be an
important point of emphasis in the time ahead.
Despite these hurdles to surmount, the emergence of evidence-based corrections is an uplifting development. Michael Lewis’s Moneyball illuminated the
power of evidence to achieve wonders in difficult circumstances. It thus created
excitement and the chance for new vistas in a sport rich in, but also burdened
by, its traditions. To be sure, a statistical, data-driven approach is not a panacea. But as in baseball, this paradigm does offer a formidable and still largely
untapped strategy for transforming the correctional landscape. In so doing,
advocates of evidence-based corrections have the potential to improve offenders’
lives and to enhance public safety. This is a worthy adventure to join.
REFERENCES
Andrews, D. A., & Bonta, J. (2006). The psychology of criminal conduct (4th ed.).
Cincinnati, OH: Anderson Publishing.
Ayres, I. (2007). Super crunchers: Why thinking-by-numbers is the new way to be smart.
New York: Bantam Books.
Berwick, D. M., Calkins, D. R., McCannon, C. J., & Hackbarth, A. D. (2006). The
100,000 lives campaign: Setting a goal and a deadline for improving health care
quality. Journal of the American Medical Association, 295, 324–327.
Bonta, J. (1996). Risk-needs assessment and treatment. In A. T. Harland (Ed.), Choosing correctional options that work: Defining the demand and evaluating the supply
(pp. 18–32). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Cullen, F. T. (2005). The twelve people who saved rehabilitation: How the science of
criminology made a difference—The American Society of Criminology 2004 presidential address. Criminology, 43, 1–42.
Cullen, F. T., Blevins, K. R., Trager, J. S., & Gendreau, P. (2005). The rise and fall of
boot camps: A case study in common-sense corrections. Journal of Offender Rehabilitation, 40(3–4), 53–70.
Cullen, F. T., & Gendreau, P. (2000). Assessing correctional rehabilitation: Policy, practice, and prospects. In J. Horney (Ed.), Criminal justice 2000: Vol. 3. Policies, processes, and decisions of the criminal justice system (pp. 109–175). Washington, DC:
National Institute of Justice, U.S. Department of Justice.
Cullen, F. T., & Gendreau, P. (2001). From nothing works to what works: Changing
professional ideology in the 21st century. Prison Journal, 81, 313–338.
Cullen, F. T., Pratt, T. C., Micelli, S. L., & Moon, M. M. (2002). Dangerous liaison?
Rational choice theory as the basis for correctional intervention. In A. R. Piquero &
S. G. Tibbetts (Eds.), Rational choice and criminal behavior: Recent research and
future challenges (pp. 279–296). New York: Routledge.
Daugherty, P. (2008, March 9). Baker judges by his senses: Knowing what makes his
players tick more important than their stats. Cincinnati Enquirer, pp. C1, C10.
211
212
F. T. Cullen, A. J. Myer, and E. J. Latessa
Davies, P. (1999). What is evidence-based education? British Journal of Educational
Studies, 47, 108–121.
Gendreau, P. (1996). The principles of effective intervention with offenders. In A. T.
Harland (Ed.), Choosing correctional options that work: Defining the demand and
evaluating the supply (pp. 117–130). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Gendreau, P., Goggin, C., Cullen, F. T., & Paparozzi, M. (2002). The common-sense revolution and correctional policy. In J. McGuire (Ed.), Offender rehabilitation and
treatment: Effective programmes and policies to reduce re-offending (pp. 359–386).
Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons.
Gendreau, P., Little, T., & Goggin, C. (1996). A meta-analysis of the predictors of adult
offender recidivism: What works! Criminology, 34, 575–607.
Gendreau, P., Smith, P., & French, S. A. (2006). The theory of effective correctional
intervention: Empirical status and future directions. In F. T. Cullen, J. P. Wright,
& K. R. Blevins (Eds.), Taking stock: The status of criminological theory—Advances
in criminological theory: Vol. 15. (pp. 419–446). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.
Gilgun, J. F. (2005). The four consequences of evidence-based practice in social work.
Research on Social Work Practice, 15, 52–61.
Gottfredson, M. R. (1979). Treatment destruction techniques. Journal of Research in
Crime and Delinquency, 16, 39–54.
Gray, S. (2006). The mind of Bill James: How a complete outsider changed baseball.
New York: Doubleday.
Guyatt, G., & The Evidence-Based Medicine Working Group. (1992). Evidence-based
medicine: A new approach to teaching the practice of medicine. Journal of the
American Medical Association, 268, 2420–2425.
Hagan, J. (1973). Labeling and deviance: A case study in the “sociology of the interesting.”
Social Problems, 20, 447–458.
Hall, S., Szymanski, S., & Zimbalist, A. S. (2002). Testing causality between team
performance and payroll: The cases of major league baseball and English soccer.
Journal of Sports Economics, 3, 149–168.
Latessa, E. J., Cullen, F. T., & Gendreau, P. (2002). Beyond correctional quackery:
Professionalism and the possibility of effective treatment. Federal Probation,
66(3), 43–49.
Leonhardt, D. (2005, August 28). Arguing baseball: To play is the thing. New York
Times, pp. 4–1, 4–4.
Lewis, M. (2003). Moneyball: The art of winning an unfair game. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Lipsey, M. W., & Cullen, F. T. (2007). The effectiveness of correctional rehabilitation: A
review of systematic reviews. Annual Review of Law and Social Sciences, 3, 297–320.
MacKenzie, D. L. (2001). Evidence-based corrections: Identifying what works. Crime
and Delinquency, 46, 457–471.
MacKenzie, D. L. (2006). What works in corrections: Reducing the criminal activities of
offenders and delinquents. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Merton, R. K. (1972). Insiders and outsiders: A chapter in the sociology of knowledge.
American Journal of Sociology, 78, 9–47.
Palmer, T. (2002). Individualized intervention with young multiple offenders. New York:
Routledge.
Moneyball
Pfeffer, J., & Sutton, R. J. (2006). Evidence-based management. Harvard Business
Review, 84(1), 62–74.
Roberts, A. R., & Yeager, K. R. (Eds.). (2004). Evidence-based practice manual:
Research and outcome measures in health and human services. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Rothman, D. J. (2007, November 19). The questions cure. The New Republic, 237, 52–55.
Rychetnik, L., Hawe, P., Waters, E., Barratt, A., & Frommer, M. (2004). A glossary for
evidence based public health. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 58,
538–545.
Sackett, D. L., & Rosenberg, W. M. C. (1995). The need for evidence-based medicine.
Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 88, 620–624.
Schwarz, A. (2004). The numbers game: Baseball’s lifelong fascination with statistics.
New York: Thomas Dunne Books.
Sherman, L. J. (1998). Evidence-based policing. Washington, DC: Police Foundation.
Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2003, September 1). Who’s on first? The New Republic,
229, 27–30.
Timmerman, S., & Berg, M. (2003). The gold standard: The challenge of evidence-based
medicine and standardization of health care. Philadelphia: Temple University
Press.
Van Voorhis, P. (1987). Correctional effectiveness: The high cost of ignoring success.
Federal Probation, 51(1), 59–62.
Welsh, B. C., & Farrington, D. P. (Eds.). (2006). Preventing crime: What works with
children, offenders, victims, and places. New York: Springer.
Wiseman, F., & Chatterjee, S. (2003). Team payroll and team performance in major
league baseball: 1985–2002. Economics Bulletin, 1, 1–10.
Wolf, F. M. (2000). Lessons to be learned from evidence-based medicine: Practice and
promise of evidence-based medicine and evidence-based education. Medical
Teacher, 22, 251–259.
213
Purchase answer to see full
attachment