PHI 3633 St Thomas University Week 5 Biomedical Ethics Vital Organs Paper

User Generated

whyvrguebqevthrm

Health Medical

PHI 3633

ST Thomas University

PHI

Description

Vital Organs / Unconscious State


After studying the course materials

https://youtu.be/gRalT9DrB-U

https://youtu.be/CeAXvGHsRnY

PDFs attachment

  1. Name some very important organs that are not vital organs.
  2. List the functional description of all the normal vital organs, including today’s exceptions.
  3. Is it possible to live without a vital organ? Why? Example?
  4. Distinction between assisting or substituting vital organs. Bioethical analysis.
  5. Do the following practices assist or substitute the vital organ? Why?
    • Dialysis
    • Respirator
    • Ventilator
    • Tracheotomy
    • CPR
  6. Read and summarize ERD PART FIVE Introduction.
  7. Unconscious state: Definition.
  8. Clinical definitions of different states of unconsciousness: Compare and contrast
  9. Benefit vs Burden: bioethical analysis.

Submission Instructions:

  • The paper is to be clear and concise and students will lose points for improper grammar, punctuation, and misspelling.
  • If references are used, please cite properly according to the current APA style. Refer to your syllabus for further detail or contact your instructor.

Unformatted Attachment Preview

BIOETHICAL ISSUES TOWARD THE END OF HUMAN LIFE • TRILLIONS OF CELLS • VITAL ORGANS • MAJOR CAUSES OF DEATH • DISTINCTION BETWEEN ASSISTING OR SUBSTITUTING VITAL ORGANS REVIEW: BIOLOGICAL UNIT OF LIFE = CELL LEVELS OF BIOLOGICAL ORGANIZATION (HIERARCHY OF LIFE): CELLS -> TISSUES -> ORGANS -> SYSTEMS (ORGAN SYSTEMS) -> ORGANISM (INDIVIDUAL) • VITAL ORGANS VITAL ORGANS: • BRAIN • BRAIN STEM • BOTH LUNGS • HEART • LIVER • PANCREAS • STOMACH • SMALL INTESTINE • LARGE INTESTINE • BOTH KIDNEYS • MAJOR CAUSES OF DEATH 15 Major Causes of Death (USA) % Primary Organ 1. Diseases of the heart 28.5 HEART 2. Malignant tumors 22.8 ANY VITAL ORGAN 3. Cerebrovascular diseases 6.7 BRAIN 4. Chronic lower respiratory diseases 5.1 LUNGS 5. Accidents (unintentional injuries) 4.4 ANY VITAL ORGAN 6. Diabetes mellitus (Type II Diabetes) 3 PANCREAS 7. Influenza and pneumonia 2.7 LUNGS 8. Alzheimer’s disease 2.4 BRAIN 9. Nephritis, nephrotic syndrome and nephrosis 1.7 KIDNEYS 10. Septicemia (blood poisoning) 1.4 BLOOD 11. Suicide 1.3 ANY VITAL ORGAN 12. Chronic liver disease and cirrhosis 1.1 LIVER 13. Primary hypertension and hypertensive renal disease 0.8 ANY VITAL ORGAN 14. Parkinson’s disease (tied) 0.7 BRAIN 15. Homicide (tied) 0.7 ANY VITAL ORGAN All others 16.7 ANY VITAL ORGAN 100 (Source: CDC/NHS National Vital Statistics System) • DISTINCTION BETWEEN ASSISTING OR SUBSTITUTING VITAL ORGANS DIALYSIS: SUBSTITUTES KIDNEYS RESPIRATOR; ASSISTS IN PROVIDING OXYGEN VENTILATOR; DEPENDS ON THE SETTINGS: ASSIST OR SUBSTITUTE BREATHING RESPIRATORS: ASSIST BREATHING (NOT VENTILATOR) VENTILATOR: PERFUSION WEANING PROCESS VENT ~ 2-3 WEEKS BEFORE TRACHEOTOMY EXTUBATION TRACHEOTOMY (TRACHEOSTOMY) CARDIOPULMONARY RESUSCITATION (CPR): • ASSISTS / SUBSTITUTES HEART Defibrillation Automated External Defibrillator (AED) Implantable Cardioverter Defibrillator (ICD) Wearable Cardioverter Defibrillator (WCD) • treatment for cardiac dysrhythmias • Ex. ventricular fibrillation (VF) and ventricular tachycardia (VT) • delivers a dose of electric current to the heart • VITAL ORGANS • DISTINCTION BETWEEN ASSISTING OR SUBSTITUTING VITAL ORGANS • ASSISTING VITAL ORGANS GENERALLY OBLIGATES BIOETHICALLY • SUBSTITUTING VITAL ORGANS GENERALLY DOES NOT OBLIGATE The Unconscious States Awareness of self and the environment: internal / external (difficulties) (lack of response to painful stimulus) clinical definitions of: • coma (Glasgow Coma Scale) (induced coma) • persistent vegetative state (PVS) • traumatic head injury • brain hypoxia • epileptic seizure • syncope • other unconscious states (ex. Locked-in syndrome) CONSCIOUSNESS: Awareness of self and the environment: internal / external (difficulties; how to measure?) UNCONSCIOUSNESS: Lack of response to painful stimulus Coma (Glasgow Coma Scale) (induced coma) persistent (permanent) vegetative state (PVS) VS MCS MAGNETIC RESONANCE IMAGING (MRI) Traumatic Brain Injury (TBI) • complex injury • broad spectrum of symptoms • and disabilities Mayo Clinic: TraumaticBrainInjury.com TBI mild ~ 30 min. severe Brain Hypoxia (anoxia) 3 PAIRS OF ARTERIES TO THE HEAD: • 1 PAIR VERTEBRAL • 2 PAIRS CAROTID Epileptic Seizure (epileptic fit) Neuronal activity: • • • • Abnormal Excessive Generalized Synchronous Electro-EncephaloGram (EEG) Syncope (fainting): • Temporary loss of consciousness • Sudden drop in blood pressure Other unconscious states: • Non-epileptic seizure • Locked-in syndrome • Etc. LOCKED-IN SYNDROME: • Aware • cannot move or communicate verbally • complete paralysis of nearly all voluntary muscles • Except for vertical eye movements and blinking Damage to specific portions of the lower brain and brainstem, with no damage to the upper brain (cerebral cortex). MAGNETIC RESONANCE IMAGING (MRI) POSITRON EMISSION TOMOGRAPHY (PET) COMPUTED TOMOGRAPHY (CT) VEGETATIVE STATE MINIMALLY CONSCIOUS STATE LOCKED-IN SYNDROME (MRI) DIAGNOSIS -> PROGNOSIS MANAGEMENT, RELIEF: PAIN / SUFFERING BIOETHICAL ANALYSIS: BENEFIT / BURDEN BIOETHICAL MEANS OF LIFE SUPPORT: • ORDINARY (PROPORTIONATE) / EXTRAORDINARY (DISPROPORTIONATE) CLINICAL MEANS OF LIFE SUPPORT: • STANDARD MEDICAL PRACTICE / EXPERIMENTAL TREATMENT ETHICAL OBLIGATION RE. VITAL ORGANS: ASSIST / SUBSTITUTE WHEN TO WITHHOLD OR WITHDRAW LIFE SAVING TREATMENT? ERD 32. While every person is obliged to use ordinary means to preserve his or her health, no person should be obliged to submit to a health care procedure that the person has judged, with a free and informed conscience, not to provide a reasonable hope of benefit without imposing excessive risks and burdens on the patient or excessive expense to family or community. 33. The well-being of the whole person must be taken into account in deciding about any therapeutic intervention or use of technology. Therapeutic procedures that are likely to cause harm or undesirable side-effects can be justified only by a proportionate benefit to the patient 56. A person has a moral obligation to use ordinary or proportionate means of preserving his or her life. Proportionate means are those that in the judgment of the patient offer a reasonable hope of benefit and do not entail an excessive burden or impose excessive expense on the family or the community. 57. A person may forgo extraordinary or disproportionate means of preserving life. Disproportionate means are those that in the patient’s judgment do not offer a reasonable hope of benefit or entail an excessive burden, or impose excessive expense on the family or the community. When to Disconnect? Bioethical Distinction between Assisting or Substituting Vital Organs Rev. Alfred Cioffi, SThD, PhD Institute for Bioethics St. Thomas University Miami Gardens, Florida Introduction Without a doubt, in the United States, life expectancy has been steadily increasing over the past half century: in 1950, the average life span for Americans was about 68.2 years; in 2015, it was 79.1.i As more people tend to live into old age, we are experiencing a larger number of patients on life support systems toward the end of their life. For example, a Frontline report of the Public Broadcast System recently stated that nearly 70% of all Americans die in a hospital, nursing home or long-term care facility.ii Often, persons who have a terminal illness or are approaching the end of their life, and their loved ones, do not know how much treatment is too much, and they struggle as to when to finally stop treatment and allow the patient to die in peace.iii Conversely, healthcare professionals during such times may tend to slide into “extraordinary means” of life support –bioethically speaking– perhaps simply due to legal/fiscal concerns regarding potential lawsuits, or due to the patients’ family requesting futile care. iv A general bioethical principle that is very useful in these situations is the fact that there is no moral obligation to substitute vital organs. Substituting a vital organ, in this context, means totally replacing the vital function of the dying organ, with either a transplant or with medical machinery. v This article seeks to explain how this rule may be applied in deciding when to stop treatment, and thus allow a patient to die in peace. Vital Organs By definition, a functioning vital organ is essential for maintaining life. Examples of vital organs in the human body are: brain, brain stem, heart, both lungs, liver, whole stomach, whole intestines, pancreas, both kidneys. It is well known that, once the death process has begun, each one of these vital organs has an expected lifespan, in terms of minutes or hours, even after the brain and stem have stopped functioning irreversibly. For example, without oxygen, within the range of minutes, the lifespan of a human brain may be less than four to six minutesvi; for the heart, within twenty minutes.vii In the range of hours could be the stomach, intestines, liver and kidneys.viii It is also well known that each vital organ of the human body functioning by itself is not sufficient to maintain life; rather, each one of these organs must function within its proper organ system, and all systems must be integrated –by the nervous system– so as to maintain human life. The Death Process Regardless of how long each vital organ may last after anoxia (lack of oxygen), when a vital organ begins to fail irreversibly, one can say that the death process has begun. One may never kill an innocent being, but one may allow a person to die.ix When a moral dictate is not clear to some, it helps to pose the statement in the reverse. For example, imagine if we could not allow people to die; that is an untenable situation! Therefore, morally, one may allow people to die. One may have to provide the means possible for the dying person to die in peace, but one may certainly allow a dying person to die. Hence, whenever a vital organ begins to fail irreversibly, we can say that the dying process has begun for that person. Family and friends, and the healthcare professionals attending the dying person, in conscience, may allow that person to die in peace. Clinically, this may include disconnecting vital support systems, save those that are merely assisting the patient (i.e., a respirator, a Foley, or analgesics). Assisting versus Substituting Morally speaking, it is essential to distinguish between assisting or substituting vital organs. In other words, assisting vital organs may be considered standard medical practice, or the standard of care, including the normal use of clinical procedures, devices and/or medications. Bioethically, these are ordinary means of life support because they are considered vital or necessary for maintaining life.x However, when it comes to substituting one or more vital organs, this typically involves more elaborate clinical equipment and procedures, including such sophistications as general anesthesia and surgery. Typically this becomes extraordinary means of life support and, by definition, does not oblige morally.xi Essentially, the reason why extraordinary means are not obligatory is because all vital organs fail naturally sooner or later; experience inexorably demonstrates that to be so.xii When this is so, there is no moral obligation to substitute the dying organ(s) with a healthy one, or equivalent devices or machinery. General Moral Obligation There is a bioethical obligation to assist vital organs when possible, but there is no moral obligation to substitute vital organs when failing irreversibly. Again, when a moral dictate is not clear, it helps to pose the statement in the reverse. For example, imagine if there was a moral obligation to substitute all vital organs when failing irreversibly; that too is untenable! Therefore, there is no moral obligation to substitute vital organs when failing irreversibly. One may try to substitute them (i.e., transplants), xiii but there is no moral obligation to do so. Exception A possible exception to this bioethical principle is when certain vital organs are failing in an otherwise healthy person, and a temporary substitution presents a positive prognosis. For example, the otherwise healthy person with pneumonia who, as a patient, becomes intubated. One could argue that the ventilator is indeed substituting the lungs, at least at first, but the hope is that this intubation be temporary. Another example could be dialysis, at least until a matching kidney is found. So, for certain vital organs and under certain conditions, one can understand that a temporary substitution of a failing vital organ may obligate morally. Even so, it is also important to further distinguish between short term and long term protocols. For example, the intubation of a pneumonia or COPD patient may be considered short term (typically, one to two weeksxiv), whereas dialysis in a patient with renal failure –considering the current extended waiting lists for renal transplants– may be indeed long term (typically, in the range of years xv). In such long term protocols, an argument could me made that there may come a time when these procedures no longer obligate, bioethically speaking. This is also an area where one finds a possible discrepancy between standard clinical practice (i.e., dialysis) and morally extraordinary means (i.e., substitution of failed kidneys). In such cases, prudence calls for a patient-bypatient assessment, including such factors as age, blood type, genetic makeup, and even the patient’s own subjective estimation of how burdensome the procedure is becoming. xvi Conclusion Sometimes, patients in healthcare facilities or at home, and their loved ones, just do not know when to stop burdensome treatments. If the patient is terminal but the death process is not obvious, one can ask the attending physician; “doctor, has his/her vital organs begun to shut down irreversibly?” If the answer is, “yes,” then treatments may be stopped morally. Bioethically, comfort care always obligates, and this patient can then be allowed to die in peace. i http://www.data360.org/dsg.aspx?Data_Set_Group_Id=195, accessed 5 June 2016 http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/facing-death/facts-and-figures/, accessed 5 June 2016 ii iii Rodriguez KL, Young AJ. Patients' and healthcare providers' understandings of lifesustaining treatment: are perceptions of goals shared or divergent? Soc Sci Med. 2006 Jan;62(1):125-33 iv Willmott L1, et al., Reasons doctors provide futile treatment at the end of life: a qualitative study.Med Ethics. 2016 May 17. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2016-103370. [Epub ahead of print] v Please note that, for bioethical purposes, the emphasis is on the function of the vital organ, rather than on its structure. Thus, a dialysis machine substitutes the kidneys functionally; conversely, one can say that a transplanted heart that has been rejected by the patient’s body, has failed so substitute the dying heart functionally, even though the structural substitution was successful. vi http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/ency/article/000013.htm, accessed 5 June 2016 vii http://www.pathology.washington.edu/research/labs/murry/index.php?a=research&p=inf o, accessed 5 June 2016 viii http://www.dcids.org/facts-about-donation/frequently-asked-questions/, accessed 5 June 2016 ix Declaration on Euthanasia, Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (1980), Section IV x Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health Care Services (Fifth Ed.), US Conference of Catholic Bishops (2009), No. 56 xi ERD, 57 xii It is not the scope of this article to delve into why, if all living cells posses an inherent reparatory mechanism, do all vital organs end up failing sooner or later. For inquiry into this topic, the reader may look up: telomeres and cellular aging. xiii ERD, 63 xiv http://www.nhlbi.nih.gov/health/health-topics/topics/vent/whoneeds, accessed 5 June 2016 xv http://www.kidneylink.org/TheWaitingList.aspx, accessed 5 June 2016 xvi ERD, 27
Purchase answer to see full attachment
User generated content is uploaded by users for the purposes of learning and should be used following Studypool's honor code & terms of service.

Explanation & Answer

Find attached work. Please let me know if everything is ok. I will be happy to help with more assignments in the future. Thank you. Goodbye for now.

Running Head: VITAL ORGANS

1

Vital Organs
Student’s Name:
Institution:
Lecturer:

VITAL ORGANS

2

Question 1
The skin, eye, ears, and the reproductive organs are important for the body functioning
but are not vital organs. They are referred to as functional organs that assist in specific operations
of the body, and damaging part of them does not necessarily lead to loose of life.
Question 2
Vital organs are those that the human body depends on for its functioning, therefore,
people cannot survive without them. They include the lungs, the heart, the brain, kidneys, liver,
and the stomach and its intestines. The lungs are functional for respiration, and the heart pumps
the blood, which carries red blood cells, and waste products, to all parts of the body. The brain
controls all body functions, and receives, and omits information. Besides, the stomach and its
intestines digest foods and absorb the requir...


Anonymous
Nice! Really impressed with the quality.

Studypool
4.7
Trustpilot
4.5
Sitejabber
4.4

Similar Content

Related Tags