PHIL 311 Professional Ethics Spring 2021
Final Exam
Below are the essay prompts for your final exam. You should submit one document – 3.5 pages
total – that contain both answers (choose one from the first set, and you must answer the second).
Be sure to identify which prompt you are responding to at the start of each answer.
First Essay Prompts: Pick 1 of 2 (40 points total).
Limit your answer to the prompt you choose to 1.5 pages. You can offer supporting quotes from
relevant readings, but be sure to provide in-text citations for those quotes. You do not need to
provide a full reference, provided you are using readings assigned for class. Be conscientious of
basic essay writing format (include a basic thesis, along with relevant paragraph breaks).
Prompt 1: Whistleblowing & Responsibility
Compare and contrast the two justifications for whistleblowing (the standard theory and
the complicity theory, from Davis) - what are their central similarities and differences?
Which view is stronger, and why? Be precise; explain with reference to an example from
one of the readings from your professional case studies assigned in class.
Prompt 2: Responsibility in the Profession
Explain the argument for why professionals should still have ethical responsibility
despite lacking full knowledge (from Luban). Then, give two of the five obligations to
prevent harm, explaining and applying both in the context of one of the readings for your
professional case studies assigned in class.
Second Essay Prompt: Must answer the following prompt (60 points).
Limit your answer to 2 pages. You can offer supporting quotes from relevant readings, but be
sure to provide in-text citations for those quotes. You do not need to provide a full reference,
provided you are using readings assigned for class. Be conscientious of basic essay writing
format (include a basic thesis, along with relevant paragraph breaks).
Prompt 3: Ethically Responsible Professionals
Drawing from the ideas we explored through the course, present an argument that
answers the following question: what are the four MOST important aspects to being
an ethically responsible professional? Address this question in terms of obligations to
others (the people in need of expertise), and in terms of obligation to self (the person who
maintains a sense of personal integrity within a structure that may make such ethical
practice difficult). Present an ARGUMENT for why these four are the MOST important
(you will need to be able to explain them with reference to supporting sources, and
defend their importance).
Personal, Professional, and Institutional Obligations
WHISTLEBLOWING I*
Sissela Bok
Written by a prominent authority on applied ethics, this selection discusses the moral
conflicts involved in employees “going public” with information about misconduct in
their own organizations. Bok sees the problem of whistleblowing essentially in terms of
clashes between personal and group loyalties and public interests.
“Whistleblowing” is a new label generated by our increased awareness of the
ethical conflicts encountered at work. Whistleblowers sound an alarm from within the
very organization in which they work, aiming to spotlight neglect or abuses that threaten
the public interest.
The stakes in whistleblowing are high. Take the nurse who alleges that physicians
enrich themselves in her hospital through unnecessary surgery; the engineer who dis
closes safety defects in the braking systems of a fleet of new rapid-transit vehicles; the
Defense Department official who alerts Congress to military graft and overspend ing: All
know that they pose a threat to those whom they denounce and that their own careers may
be at risk..
Moral Conflicts
Moral conflicts on several levels confront anyone who is wondering whether to
speak out about abuses or risks or serious neglect. In the first place, he must try to decide
whether, other things being equal, speaking out is in fact in the public interest. This
choice is often made more complicated by factual uncertainties: Who is responsible for
the abuse or neglect? How great is the threat? And how likely is it that speaking out will
precipitate changes for the better?
In the second place, a would-be whistleblower must weigh his responsibility to
serve the public interest against the responsibility he owes to his colleagues and the
institution in which he works. While the professional ethic requires collegial loyalty, the
codes of ethics often stress responsibility to the public over and above duties to
colleagues and clients. Thus the United States Code of Ethics for Government Servants
asks them to “expose corruption wherever uncovered” and to “put loyalty to the highest
moral principles and to country above loyalty to persons, party, or government.”
Similarly, the largest professional engineering association re quires members to speak out
against abuses threatening the safety, health, and welfare of the public.†
*
†
References have been deleted without indication.
For the Code of Ethics of the National Society of Professional Engineering, see Appendix II in this book.
From Sissela Bok, “Wiistleblowing and Professional Responsibility,” in the New York University
Education Quarterly 11:4 (1980): 2-10. Reprinted by permission.
A third conflict for would-be whistle- blowers is personal in nature and cuts across the
first two: Even in cases where they have concluded that the facts warrant speaking out,
and that their duty to do so overrides loyalties to colleagues and institutions, they often
have reason to fear the results of carrying out such a duty. How ever strong this duty may
seem in theory, they know that, in practice, retaliation is likely. As a result, their careers
and their ability to support themselves and their families may be unjustly impaired. A
government handbook issued during the Nixon era recommends reassigning
“undesirables” to places so remote that they would prefer to resign. Whistleblowers may
also be downgraded or given work without responsibility or work for which they are not
qualified; or else they may be given many more tasks than they can possibly perform.
Another risk is that an outspoken civil servant may be ordered to undergo a psychiatric
fitness-for-duty examination, declared unfit for service, and “separated” as well as
discredited from the point of view of any allegations he may be making. Outright firing,
finally, is the most direct institutional response to whistleblowers.
Add to the conflicts confronting individual whistleblowers the claim to selfpolicing that many professions make, and professional responsibility is at issue in still
another way. For an appeal to the public goes against everything that “self-policing”
stands for. The question for the different professions, then, is how to resolve, insofar as it
is possible, the conflict between professional loyalty and professional responsibility
toward the outside world. The same conflicts arise to some extent in all groups, but
professional groups often have special cohesion and claim special dignity and privileges.
The plight of whistleblowers has come to be documented by the press and de
scribed in a number of books. Evidence of the hardships imposed on those who chose to
act in the public interest has combined with a heightened awareness of professional
malfeasance and corruption to pro duce a shift toward greater public support of
whistleblowers. Public service law firms and consumer groups have taken up their cause;
institutional reforms and legislation have been proposed to combat illegitimate reprisals.
Given the indispensable services per formed by so many whistleblowers, strong
support is often merited. But the new climate of acceptance makes it easy to over look the
dangers of whistleblowing: of uses in error or in malice; of work and reputations unjustly
lost for those falsely accused; of privacy invaded and trust under-mined. There comes a
level of internal prying and mutual suspicion at which no institution can function. And it
is a fact that the disappointed, the incompetent, the malicious, and the paranoid all too
often leap to accusations in public. Worst of all, ideological persecution throughout the
world traditionally relies on insiders willing to inform on their colleagues or even on their
family members, often through staged public denunciations or press campaigns.
No society can count itself immune from such dangers. But neither can it risk
silencing those with a legitimate reason to blow the whistle. How then can we distinguish
between different instances of whistleblowing? A society that fails to protect the right to
speak out even on the part of those whose warnings turn out to be spurious obviously
opens the door to political repression. But from the moral point of view there are
important differences between the aims, messages, and methods of dissenters from
within.
Nature of Whistleblowing
Three elements, each jarring, and triply jarring when conjoined, lend acts of
whistleblowing special urgency and bitterness:
dissent, breach of loyalty, and accusation. Like all dissent, whistleblowing makes public a
disagreement with an authority or a majority view. But whereas dissent can concern all
forms of disagreement with, for instance, religious dogma or government policy or court
decisions, whistle- blowing has the narrower aim of shedding light on negligence or
abuse, or alerting to a risk, and of assigning responsibility for this risk.
Would-be whistleblowers confront the conflict inherent in all dissent: between
conforming and sticking their necks out. The more repressive the authority they
challenge, the greater the personal risk they take in speaking out. At exceptional times, as
in times of war, even ordinarily tolerant authorities may come to regard dissent as
unacceptable and even disloyal.
Furthermore, the whistleblower hopes to stop the game; but since he is neither
referee nor coach, and since he blows the whistle on his own team, his act is seen as a
violation of loyalty. In holding his position, he has assumed certain obligations to his
colleagues and clients. He may even have subscribed to a loyalty oath or a promise of
confidentiality. Loyalty to colleagues and to clients comes to be pitted against loyalty to
the public interest, to those who may be injured unless the revelation is made.
Not only is loyalty violated in whistle- blowing, hierarchy as well is often
opposed, since the whistleblower is not only a colleague but a subordinate. Though aware
of the risks inherent in such disobedience, he often hopes to keep his job. At times,
however, he plans his alarm to coincide with leaving the institution. If he is highly
placed, or joined by others, resigning in protest may effectively direct public attention to
the wrongdoing at issue. Still an other alternative, often chosen by those who wish to be
safe from retaliation, is to leave the institution quietly, to secure an other post, and then to
blow the whistle. In this way, it is possible to speak with the authority and knowledge of
an insider with out having the vulnerability of that position.
It is the element of accusation, of calling a “foul,” that arouses the strongest
reactions on the part of the hierarchy. The accusation may be of neglect, of willfully
concealed dangers, or of outright abuse on the part of colleagues or superiors. It singles
out specific persons or groups as responsible for threats to the public interest. If no one
could be held responsible — as in the case of an impending avalanche — the warning
would not constitute whistleblowing.
The accusation of the whistleblower, moreover, concerns a present or an
imminent threat. Past errors or misdeeds occasion such an alarm only if they still affect
current practices. And risks far in the future lack the immediacy needed to make the
alarm a compelling one, as well as the close connection to particular individuals that
would justify actual accusations. Thus an alarm can be sounded about safety defects in a
rapid-transit system that threaten or will shortly threaten passengers, but the revelation of
safety defects in a system no longer in use, while of historical interest, would not
constitute whistleblowing. Nor would the revelation of potential problems in a system not
yet fully designed and far from implemented.
Not only immediacy, but also specificity, is needed for there to be an alarm
capable of pinpointing responsibility. A concrete risk must be at issue rather than a vague
foreboding or a somber prediction. The act of whistleblowing differs in this respect from
the lamentation or the dire prophecy. An immediate and specific threat would normally
be acted upon by those at risk. The whistleblower assumes that his message will alert
listeners to something they do not know, or whose significance they have not grasped
because it has been kept secret.
The desire for openness inheres in the temptation to reveal any secret, sometimes
joined to an urge for self-aggrandizement and publicity and the hope for revenge for past
slights or injustices. There can be plea sure, too — righteous or malicious — in laying
bare the secrets of co-workers and in setting the record straight at last. Col leagues of the
whistleblower often suspect his motives: they may regard him as a crank, as publicityhungry, wrong about the facts, eager for scandal and discord, and driven to indiscretion
by his personal biases and shortcomings.
For whistleblowing to be effective, it must arouse its audience. Inarticulate
whistleblowers are likely to fail from the outset. When they are greeted by apathy, their
message dissipates. When they are greeted by disbelief, they elicit no response at all. And
when the audience is not free to receive or to act on the information — when censorship
or fear of retribution stifles response — then the message rebounds to injure the
whistleblower. Whistleblowing also requires the possibility of concerted public response:
The idea of whistleblowing in an anarchy is therefore merely quixotic.
Such characteristics of whistleblowing and strategic considerations for achieving
an impact are common to the noblest warnings, the most vicious personal attacks, and the
delusions of the paranoid. How can one distinguish the many acts of sounding an alarm
that are genuinely in the public interest from all the petty, biased, or lurid revelations that
pervade our querulous and gossip-ridden society? Can we draw distinctions between
different whistleblowers, different messages, different methods?
We clearly can, in a number of cases. Whistleblowing may be starkly
inappropriate when in malice or error, or when it lays bare legitimately private matters
having to do, for instance, with political belief or sexual life. It can, just as clearly, be the
only way to shed light on an ongoing unjust practice such as drugging political prisoners
or subjecting them to electroshock treatment. It can be the last resort for alerting the
public to an impending disaster. Taking such clearcut cases as bench marks, and
reflecting on what it is about them that weighs so heavily for or against speaking out, we
can work our way toward the admittedly more complex cases in which whistleblowing is
not so clearly the right or wrong choice, or where different points of view exist regarding
its legitimacy — cases where there are moral reasons both for concealment and for
disclosure and where judgments conflict. Consider the following cases:
1. As a construction inspector for a federal agency, John Samuels (not his real name)
had personal knowledge of shoddy and deficient construction practices by private
con tractors. He knew his superiors received free vacations and entertainment, had
their homes remodeled and found jobs for their relatives — all courtesy of a
private contractor. These superiors later approved a multimillion no-bid contract
with the same “generous” firm. Samuels also had evidence that other firms were
hiring nonunion laborers at a low wage while receiving substantially higher
payments from the government for labor costs. A former superior, unaware of an
office dicta- phone, had incautiously instructed Samuels on how to accept bribes
for overlooking sub- par performance.As he prepared to volunteer this
information to various members of Congress, he became tense and uneasy. His
family was scared and the fears were valid. It might cost Samuels thousands of
dollars to protect his job. Those who had freely provided Samuels with
information would probably recant or withdraw their friendship. A number of
people might object to his using a Dictaphone to gather information. His agency
would start covering up and vent its collective wrath upon him. As for reporters
and writers, they would gather for a few days, then move on to the next story. He
would be left without a job, with fewer friends, with massive battles looming, and
without the financial means of fighting them. Samuels decided to remain silent.
2. Engineers of Company “A” prepared plans and specifications for machinery to be
used in a manufacturing process and Company “A” turned them over to Company
“B” for production. The engineers of Company “B,” in reviewing the plans and
specifications, came to the conclusion that they included certain miscalculations
and technical deficiencies of a nature that the final product might be unsuitable
for the purposes of the ultimate users, and that the equipment, if built ac cording
to the original plans and specifications, might endanger the lives of persons in
proximity to it. The engineers of Company “B” called the matter to the attention
of appropriate officials of their employer who, in turn, advised Company “A.”
Company “A” replied that its engineers felt that the design and specifications for
the equipment were adequate and safe and that Company “B” should proceed to
build the equipment as designed and specified. The officials of Company “B”
instructed its engineers to proceed with the work.
3. A recently hired assistant director of ad missions in a state university begins to
wonder whether transcripts of some applicants accurately reflect their
accomplishments. He knows that it matters to many in the university community,
including alumni, that the football team continue its winning tradition. He has
heard rumors that surrogates may be available to take tests for a fee, signing the
names of designated applicants for admission, and that some of the transcripts
may have been altered. But he has no hard facts. When he brings the question up
with the director of admissions, he is told that the rumors are unfounded and
asked not to inquire further into the matter.
Individual Moral Choice
What questions might those who consider sounding an alarm in public ask them
selves? How might they articulate the problem they see and weigh its injustice before
deciding whether or not to reveal it? How can they best try to make sure their choice is
the right one? In thinking about these questions it helps to keep in mind the three
elements mentioned earlier: dissent, breach of loyalty, and accusation. They impose
certain requirements — of accuracy and judgment in dissent; of exploring alter native
ways to cope with improprieties that minimize the breach of loyalty; and of fair ness in
accusation. For each, careful articulation and testing of arguments are needed to limit
error and bias.
Dissent by whistleblowers, first of all, is expressly claimed to be intended to
benefit the public. It carries with it, as a result, an obligation to consider the nature of this
benefit and to consider also the possible harm that may come from speaking out:
harm to persons or institutions and, ultimately, to the public interest itself.
Whistleblowers must, therefore, begin by making every effort to consider the effects of
speaking out versus those of remaining silent. They must assure themselves of the
accuracy of their reports, checking and rechecking the facts before speaking out; specify
the degree to which there is genuine impropriety; consider how imminent is the threat
they see, how serious, and how closely linked to those accused of neglect and abuse.
If the facts warrant whistleblowing, how can the second element — breach of
loyalty — be minimized? The most important question here is whether the existing
avenues for change within the organization have been explored. It is a waste of time for
the public as well as harmful to the institution to sound the loudest alarm first.
Whistleblowing has to remain a last alter native because of its destructive side effects:
It must be chosen only when other alter natives have been considered and
rejected. They may be rejected if they simply do not apply to the problem at hand, or
when there is not time to go through routine channels, or when the institution is so
corrupt or coercive that steps will be taken to silence the whistleblower should he try the
regular channels first.
What weight should an oath or a promise of silence have in the conflict of
loyalties? One sworn to silence is doubtless under a stronger obligation because of the
oath he has taken. He has bound himself, assumed specific obligations beyond those
assumed in merely taking a new position. But even such promises can be overridden
when the public interest at issue is strong enough. They can be overridden if they were
obtained under duress or through deceit. They can be overridden, too, if they promise
something that is in itself wrong or unlawful. The fact that one has promised silence is no
excuse for complicity in covering up a crime or a violation of the public’s trust.
The third element in whistleblowing — accusation — raises equally serious ethical
concerns. They are concerns of fairness to the persons accused of impropriety. Is the
message one to which the public is entitled in the first place? Or does it infringe on
personal and private matters that one has no right to invade? Here, the very notion of
what is in the public’s best “interest” is at issue: “Accusations” regarding an official’s
unusual sexual or religious experiences may well appeal to the public’s interest without
being information relevant to “the public interest.”
Great conflicts arise here. We have witnessed excessive claims to executive
privilege and to secrecy by government officials during the Watergate scandal in order to
cover up for abuses the public had every right to discover. Conversely, those hoping to
profit from prying into private matters have become adept at invoking “the public’s right
to know.” Some even regard such private matters as threats to the public:
they voice their own religious and political prejudices in the language of accusation. Such
a danger is never stronger than when the accusation is delivered surreptitiously. The
anonymous accusations made during the McCarthy period regarding political beliefs and
associations often injured per sons who did not even know their accusers or the exact
nature of the accusations.
From the public’s point of view, accusations that are openly made by identifiable
individuals are more likely to be taken seriously. And in fairness to those criticized,
openly accepted responsibility for blowing the whistle should be preferred to the
denunciation or the leaked rumor. What is openly stated can more easily be checked, its
source’s motives challenged, and the underlying information examined. Those under
attack may otherwise be hard put to defend themselves against nameless adversaries.
Often they do not even know that they are threatened until it is too late to respond. The
anonymous denunciation, moreover, common to so many regimes, places the burden of
investigation on government agencies that may thereby gain the power of a secret police.
From the point of view of the whistle- blower, on the other hand, the anonymous
message is safer in situations where retaliation is likely. But it is also often less likely to
be taken seriously. Unless the message is accompanied by indications of how the
evidence can be checked, its anonymity, however safe for the source, speaks against it.
During this process of weighing the legitimacy of speaking out, the method used,
and the degree of fairness needed, whistleblowers must try to compensate for the strong
possibility of bias on their part. They should be scrupulously aware of any motive that
might skew their message: a desire for self-defense in a difficult bureaucratic situation,
perhaps, or the urge to seek revenge, or inflated expectations regarding the effect their
message will have on the situation. (Needless to say, bias affects the silent as well as the
outspoken. The motive for holding back important information about abuses and injustice
ought to give similar cause for soul-searching.)
Likewise, the possibility of personal gain from sounding the alarm ought to give
pause. Once again there is then greater risk of a biased message. Even if the
whistieblower regards himself as incorruptible, his profiting from revelations of neglect
or abuse will lead others to question his motives and to put less credence in his charges.
If, for example, a government employee stands to make large profits from a book
exposing the iniquities in his agency, there is danger that he will, perhaps even un
consciously, slant his report in order to cause more of a sensation.
A special problem arises when there is a high risk that the civil servant who
speaks out will have to go through costly litigation. Might he not justifiably try to make
enough money on his public revelations — say, through books or public speaking — to
off set his losses? In so doing he will not strictly speaking have profited from his
revelations:
he merely avoids being financially crushed by their sequels. He will nevertheless still be
suspected at the time of revelation, and his message will therefore seem more
questionable. Reducing bias and error in moral choice often requires consultation, even
open de bate: methods that force articulation of the moral arguments at stake and
challenge privately held assumptions. But acts of whistleblowing present special
problems when it comes to open consultation. On the one hand, once the whistleblower
sounds his alarm publicly, his arguments will be subjected to open scrutiny: He will have
to articulate his reasons for speaking out and substantiate his charges. On the other hand,
it will then be too late to retract the alarm or to combat its harmful effects, should his
choice to speak out have been ill-advised.
For this reason, the whistleblower owes it to all involved to make sure of two
things: that he has sought as much and as objective advice regarding his choice as he can
before going public; and that he is aware of the arguments for and against the practice of
whistleblowing in general, so that he can see his own choice against as richly detailed and
coherently structured a background as possible. Satisfying these two requirements once
again has special problems because of the very nature of whistleblowing: the more
corrupt the circumstances, the more dangerous it may be to seek consultation be fore
speaking out. And yet, since the whistleblower himself may have a biased view of the
state of affairs, he may choose not to consult others when in fact it would be not only safe
but advantageous to do so; he may see corruption and conspiracy where none exists.
Chapter
1 r TheNatureof Morality 45
;tions
.at business and
,f amoral busir mJth? Do you
,ct the "Three
much unethical
rday?What hapBreakers?Can
is scum" underinesspeople are
; is a practice
r" in businesstorgedin anyway?
rere is notling
ificing the botble with his
rantee tfrat
ne" (p.40)?
ReadingMORAL
RNSPoNSIBILITY
IN
THE
ACN
OF
BUREAUCRACY
Devro LuneN,Ar-eNSrnuor,en,
eNo DevroWassnnuaN
Large bureutcratic organizafiors frequently d;Iute an indioid.ual\ serce of moral responslbl,llty, and mernbersof such
mganizntions are oll too likely to acquizscein organizational misconduct. Orle reasonfor this is that irsid.e the
organization krwwledge can be sofragwnted that an lndloldad nuy be partially or whally igwrant of ushatthz mganizntion is doing. Daoid Luban, Nan Strudle4 and Daoid
Wassermand.anhw thb problem. Whcreas most moral
theoriesprewppose that thc moral agent krwtos that a ilzcision mtst be made and uhat clloices are aoailabl.e,these
wtlwrs erplore tltz moral resporxibilitizs of indfui&tals in
organizatinnal sihtotions in uhbh they lack thls krcutbdge.
such supposedly independent professionals as
physicians and lawyers practice in large organizations to an ever-increasingextent. The HMO has replaced the family physician,and the new graduates
of today'slaw schoolsjoin firms, of which the largest
now employ over a thousand lawyers, rather than
h*gng out a shingle. The problems of professional
and businessethics have thus become the problems
of supervisorsand subordinatesin organizational
settings. Indeed, in a culture such as ours, where
our first question to each other is often not "How
do you do?" but "What do you do?" the ethics of the
workplace has enormous impact on how we think
of morality in general. To a great extent, ethics in
the organizational setting has come to define ethics
as a whole. We speakof team players and loose cannons, leaders and followers, as categories of moral
judgmeni and not simply of social description.
The Organization Man and
the Other-DirectedSociety
The transformatior: of the workplace appears to
have wrought a transformation in values, replacing
individual responsibility and internal norms with
group identiffcation and external norms. As the
postwar American economy assumedits contemBACKGROUND
OFTHEPROBLEM
porary form, several leading social scientists and
The bureaucratic fragmentation of knowledge and commentators explored the psychologyof "The Ordilution of responsibfuty are pervasive phenimena
ganization Man," in the famous title of William H.
in modern society.To set the stagefor our analysis, Whyte's book. Whyte used this term to describe
we first describe the scope of the problem and "the ones of our middle classwho have left home,
briefly review some of the research, commentary
spiritually as well as physically, to take the vows of
and debate it has provoked. We conclude this back- organization li[e."r He ascribed to them the "social
ground section by discussingthe researchmost rele- EtlLic," which includes "a belief in the group as the
vant to our own concerns, the Milgram studies of source of creativity" as well as "a belief in 'belongdestructive obedience to authoritv.
ingness'asthe uliimate need of the individual,;2
David Riesman described middle-classAmericans as a "Loneiy Crowd," and elaborated a famous
TheCollectivization
of the Workplace
typolog" of characters.In Riesman'sscheme,peoMost work in modern society is done by organizaple of premodern societieswere tradition-direaed,
Uons:colporations, governments,hospitals,founand the sanction for deviation was sharne;in early
dations,universities, accounting ffrms, armies. Even
modern societies people were inner-directed,
guided by an internal moral compass, acquired
Excerpted by permission from David Lubar, Alan Strudler, and
in
childhood, which induces guilt when one deviDavid Wasserman, "Moral Responsibility ir the Age of Bureaucracy,"Mi.chigan Law Retiats g0 (August 1992). @ 1992 Michiates. In contemporary society, however, we have
gan Law Review Association.
become other-directed: our "contemDoraries are
46
andBusiness
PartOner MoralPhilosophy
the source of direction for the individual. . . . [T]he
process of paying close attention to the signals
from others . . . remainfs] unaltered throughout
life."3 For other-directed indlviduals, the sanction
for deviance has changed: "As against guilt-andshame controls, though of course these survive,
one prime psychologicallever of the other-directed
person is a diffuse anxiety."a Sociologist Robert
Jackall conducted interviews with 143 managersin
sev-eralcontemporary American corporations.In
the anxiety-ridden world of middle management,
"fm]anagers have a myriad of aphorisms that refer
to how tJrepower of CEOs, magnified through the
zealous efforts of subordinates,affects them. . . .
'When
he sneezes,we all catch
[One such maxim is]
colds'. . . ."5Jackallcomments:
As a result, independent morally evaluative judgments
get subordinated to the social intricacies of the bureaucratic wor\rlace. Notions of morality that one might hold
and indeed practice outside the workplace . . . become irrelevant. . . . Under certain conditions, such notions may
even become dangerous. For the most part, then, they
remain unarticulated lest one risk damaging crucial relationships with signiffcant individuals or groups.6
HistoricalPerspective
The collectivization of the workplace and t}e threat
it poses to traditional moral values are hardly new
phenomena; they have been recognized, and
lamented, for the past 150 years.The erosion of in&vidual responsibility and the evils of bureaucracy
have engagedconservativewriters since tle advent
of the industrial revolution. Over a century ago,
Karl Marx likewise criticized what he called "the
real mindlessnessof the state." "The bureaucracy
is a circle from which no one can escape," Marx
contended. "The highest point entrusts the understanding of particulars to the lower echelons,
whereas these, on the other hand, credit the highest with an understan&ng in regard to the universal; and thus they deceiveone another."TIn 1932,
Reinhold Niebuhr wrote his classic treattse Moral
Man and lm:nwral Society, in which he argued that
[i]ndividual men may be moral. . . . They are endowed
by nature with a measure of sympathy and consideration
for their kind, the breadth of which may be extended by
an astute social pedagory. . . . But all tlese achievements
are more difffcult, if not impossible, for human societies
and social groups. In every human group there is less
reason to guide and to check impulse, less capacity for
self-transcendence,less abi-lityto comprehend the needs
ofottrers and therefore more unrestrained egoism than
the individuals, who compose the group, reveal in their
personal relationships.s
Niebuhr's argument recognizes that the increasing
organization of society will be accompaniedby a dilution of morality.
. . . lTlhe problems Marx and Niebuhr &scussed
in a theoretical vein came to life in the most horrible
way possibleduring World War II, where ostensibly
civilized human beings tortured and slaughtered
twelve million men, women, and children in extermination camps. The names of the camPsAuschwitz, Treblinka, Majdanek-have become
slmonymouswith the incomprehensible willingness
of ordinary human beings to do anlthing, no matter
how atrocious,when ordered to do so by those in authority. Here, again, an explanation may be offered
in terms of the division of responsibility within
groups. Consider a historian's description of the
euthanasiaprogram Hitler ordered to eliminate
mentally retarded, handicapped, or genetically ill
Germans (individuals Hider called "uselesseaters"):
The euthanasia program . . . demonstrated how, through
fragmentation of authority and tasks, it was possible to
fashion a murder machine. Hitler had enunciated an offhand, extra-iegal decree, and had not wanted to be bothered about it again. Brandt had ordered the "scientific"
implementation of the program and, like Hider, wished to
hear no complaints. The directors and penonnel of krstitutiorx rationalized that matters were out of their han& and
that they were just fflling out questionnaires . . . , &ough in
realityeach form was the equivalent ofa death warrant. . ,
The oersonnel at the end of the line excusedt}emselves
on tf,e basis that they were under compulsion, had no
power of decision, and were merely performing a function.
Thousands ofpeople were involved, but each considered
himself nothing but a cog in the machine and reasoned that
it was the machine, not he, that was responsible.s
The horrors of Nazism are without parallel, but the
bureaucratic pattern of organization that fragments
the knowledge required for moral decisionmahng
is common to large institutions throughout contemporary society. Jackall describes the tlpical corporate strucfure in terms not unlike those Marx used
to characterize "&e real mindlessnessof the state":
Power is co
chief execut
centralized'
its is pushe
possible.
... [P]ur
authority to
Moreover, p
burden of
knowledge.
. . [Mid
given stratel
go wrong.lo
Hannah Are
nomenon as
alongside th
one (monar(
rule by the f
(democracy)
the latest an
minion: bun
bureaus in v
ther the few
which could
accord with
9Tanny as g(
itself, rule b1
since tlere i:
swer for whe
ize responsit
Such rumors
exaggerated;
of familiarity.
peared in liul
In his opinio
noted:
The project
particular qt
partment, tl
plains that t
quality contr
partment rel
ager was the
on that quesl
quesuons Po
able by anyo:
One must no'
of fragmentt
and cynically
utives in the
1 r TheNatureof Morality 47
Chapter
f,r human societies
foup there is less
:, less capacity for
prehend the needs
ained egoism than
'up, reveal in their
hat tle increasing
ompanied by a dirJiebuhr discussed
the most horrible
, where ostensibly
and slaughtered
children in exterof the campsk-have become
,nsiblewillingness
rything, no matter
r so by those in au)n may be offered
ronsibility within
escription of the
rred to eliminate
or genetically ill
[ "uselesseaters"):
ated how, through
it was possible to
enunciated an offsanted to be bothed the "scientific"
e Hider, wished to
enonnel of instituoftheir hands and
'ires...,thoughin
death warrant. . . .
rcused tlemselves
mpulsion, had no
brming a firnction.
rt each considered
: and reasoned that
ronsible.s
t parallel,but the
rn that fragments
I decisionmaking
oughoutcontemhe typical corpothoseMarx used
ressofthe state":
Power is concentrated at the top in the person of the
chief executive of{icer (CEO) and is simultaneously decentralized; that is, responsibility for decisions and profits is pushed as far down the organizational line as
oossible.
. . . [P]ushing details down protects the privilege of
authority to declare that a mistake has been made. . . .
Moreover, pushing down details relieves superiors of the
burden of too much knowledge, particularly guilty
knowledge.
. . [Middle managers] become t]re "point men" of a
given stratery and the potential "fall guys" when things
go wrong.ro
same skepticism that greeted German offfcials who
"didn't know." Despite this healthy skepticism,
however, we remain convinced that fraqmented
knowledge is a genuine phenomenon thaiwe cannot simply &smiss as a lame excuse.
The Psychology
of DestructiveObedience
Social scientists have labored to understand the
Holocaust and to answer the all-important question
whether it could occur in other settings. Stanley
Milgram conducted perhaps the most silnificantHannah Arendt described the bureaucratic pheand certainly t}re most famous---experimental studnomenon as a novel form ofgovernance appearing
ies to address this issue. Milgram's erperiments
alongsidethe classical distinction among rule by
underscore our thesis because they illustrate the
one (monarchy), rule by "the best" (aristocracy),
ways
in which social and institutional pressures to
rule by the few (oligarchy), and rule by the many
obey reinforce, and are reinforced by, tie fragmen(democracy).She wrote of
tation of knowledge in modern bureaucraciesand
the latest and perhaps most formidable form of. . . dootler large organizations.
minion: bureaucracy or the rule of an intricate qystem of
In Milgram's experiments, volunteers in a Yale
bureaus ia which no men, neither one nor ttre best, neiUniversity
experiment were ordered by the experither the few nor ttre many, can be held responsible, and
menter to administer gradually increasing electric
which could be properly called rule by Nobody. (If, in
accord with traditional political thought, we identifr
shocks to another "subject" (actually a confederate
q.Tanny as government that is not held to give account of
of the experimenter), ostensibly to study the effect
itself, nrle by Nobody is clearly the most lrannical of all,
of punishment on learning. As the "shocks" insince there is no one left who could even be asked to arcreased in intensity, the confederate displayed inswer for what is being done. It is . . . impossible to localcreasing discomfort, demanded that the experiment
ize responsibility and to idenUfr the enemy. . . .)rr
stop, screamed with pain, complained of a heart
Such rumors of the demise of responsibility may be condition, and ffnally fell silent as if he were unconexaggerated;yet Arendt's description has the ring scious.rs In this original experiment, sixty-five
perof familiarity. A graphic contemporary analogue ap- cent of the subjects went all the way, administering
peared in litigation surrounding the Dalkon Shield. the highest
possible, potentially lethal, level of
In his opinion, Federal Judge Frank Theis angrily
shock. Those subjects who administered the maxinoted:
mum shock erpressed geat &scomfort at the cruel
The project manager for Dalkon Shield explains that a
task they were assigned;many of them berated the
particular question should have gone to the medical deexperimenter, protested, or insisted that they would
partment, the medical department representative exnot proceed with the experiment-all the while
plains that the question was really the bailiwick of the
continuing to flip the switches.
quality control department, and the quality control deMilgram conducted a number of important
partment representative explains that the project manager was the one with the authority to make a decision
variations on the original experiment, several of
on that question. . . . [Ih is not at all unusua] for the hard
which suggest the role that incomplete and fragquestions posed in Dalkon Shield casesto be unanswermented knowledge may play in facilitating destrucable by anyone from Robins [the manufacturer].rg
tive obedience and the abdication of individual
One must not be naive, of course: often t}le defense responsibility. In one version, the experiment was
of fragmented knowledge will be entered falsely removed from the arxiety-relieving auspicesof Yale
and cynically, as a form of liability screening. Exec- to a seedy-looking storefront operation in nearby
utives in the hot seat should be treated with the Bridgeport. Less able to reassurethemselvesthat
ry
48
PartOner MoralPhilosophy
andBusiness
the experimenters knew what they were doing,
fifty-three percent ofthe subjects refused to go all
the way. This suggeststhat compliant subordinates
often believe that their qualms are merely the result of incomplete understan&ng, and assumethat
tlose in charge have good reasonsfor what they are
doing.
The rate of compliance also declined when the
subject could seethe victim, and declined even further when the subject was actually required to hold
the victim's hand on the contact-plate. In tlis latter
version of the experiment, seventy percent of the
subjects stopped before administering the maximum level of shock.. . .
Another form of ignorance that appears to have
played a significant role in Milgram's experiments
was t-heabsenceof a clear-cut moment of decision.
Few subjects would have hesitated to give a mild,
tingling shock; most probably would have refused
to give an initial shock of maximum voltage. The
gradual escalation of voltage was insidious because
it deprived subjects ofan obvious stopping point,
encouraging them to defer resistanceuntil tley saw
themselves as committed, or as compromised. This
hnd of slippery slope may characterize many of the
decisions made in contemporary organizations.
Another variant of the Milgram experiments,
however, provides some encouragement that resistance and reform may be possible ia organizational
settings. In this study, the subject was assignedto a
team administering the shocks, while the other
team members were really confederates of the experimenter. Milgram discovered that compiiance
was extraordinarily sensitive to peer pressure.
When the otler team members refused to proceed
with the experiment, only ten percent of the subjects remained obedient to the erperimenter and
"went all the way." Conversely, when a teammate
rather than the subject took charge ofphysically
administering the shock, 92.5Voof the subjects
went along with the experiment up to the maximum shock. In Niebuhr's terms, we may think of
moral man made less moral by an immoral society,
but m.oremoral by a society of his betters. . . .
The Milgram studies, then, suggestthe role of
imperfect and fragmented knowledge in organizational misconduct. The less individuals appreciate
the consequencesof tleir acts, the need to decide,
and the available alternatives, the easier it will be
for them to engagein destructive obedience. Milgramt experiments suggest that the fragmentation
of knowledge promotes organizational wrongdoing
by blunting the edge of moral conflict.
Although Milgramt research focused on subordinates, parallel problems arise for supervisors. As
we have seen,bureaucratic strucfures serye to deny
supervisorsknowledge of operational details, blunt
their awarenessofharsh consequences,and help
them rationalize what they cannot ignore. The result is the deep paradox of the "rule by Nobod/':
when neither superiors nor subordinates may be
held responsible,we face an uncanny situation in
which responsibility has seemingly been conjured
out of existence.
Thelnadequacy
of EthicalTradition
Theory
andPhilosophical
. . . We believe that the specter of fragmented
knowledge, divided responsibility, ambiguous orders, and unknown consequencesis inadequately
addressedin the moral discourseof Western societies. Virtually every approach to normative ethics,
from the Ten Commandments to the latest wrinkles
in philosophy journals, focusesprimary attention on
moral problems in which fourkrmobdge conditions
are satisfied-knowledge conditions that are frequently absent ln individual decisionmaking and almost never found in organizational settings.
Firsf, the decisionmaker recognizes that he or
she has come to a fork in the road: The decisionmaker knows that adecision must be made. Do I or
don't I cheat on the examination? Do I or don't I
protest when I hear an acquaintancetell an antiSemitic joke? Situations such as these are readily
identi{iable as moral decisions. Typically, when we
face one of these questions,we know that we face it.
Second,the decisionmaker recognizesthat he or
she must make the choice in a fairly short, distinct
period of time: The decisionmaker knows when a
decision must be made, or at least by wben it must
be made. The examination is tomorrow: I must
confront the acquaintance about his anti-Semitic
joke now or never.
Third
number
maker kr:
ple, a lar
services
Iogue he
talk the <
the clien
Fourt'
needed t
knows rp,
situationr
ories of r
allow us
various r
mendati,
merely tr
These
of moral
must be
rohat cht
make thr
steal" an
imperati
the greal
preceptr
are direr
conditior
cal syste
even im
what tht
of moral
Ignor
philosop
the pher
plicitly c
cases:c(
deniabil
themsel.
place mr
a state o
reers ha
addresse
In an
four lno
juncture
individu
Chapter
1 r TheNatureof Morality 49
re need to decide,
Leeasier it will be
e obedience, MilLhefragmentation
ional wrongdoing
rflict.
focused on suboror supervisors. As
ures serve to deny
onal details, blunt
uences, and help
rt ignore. The rerule by Nobody":
rrdinates may be
:anny situation in
y'y been conjured
dition
rr of fragmented
y, ambiguousor:sis inadequately
, of Westernsocinormativeethics,
ie latestwrinkles
mary attention on
wledgeconditiors
ions that are freonmakingand alI settings.
gnizesthat he or
rd:The decisionbe made.Do I or
? Do I or don't I
rnce tell an antitheseare readily
ryically,when we
>wthat we faceit.
rgnizesthat he or
rly short,distinct
er knowstohena
.by whenit must
,InorrowiI must
his anti-Semitic
Thi.rd, the decisionmaker confronts a small
number of well-defined options: The decisionmaker knows what choicesare available. For example, a lawyer, learning that her client is using her
services to pelpetrate a fraud, can quickly catalogue her options: do what the client asks,try to
talk the client out of the plan, blow the whistle on
the client, or resign.
Fourth, the decisionmaker has the information
needed to make the decision: The decisionmaker
lcnowsuhat is need.edto make the choice. Even in
situations of radically incomplete information, tlleories of rational decisionmahng under uncertainty
allow us to assign probabillty-estimates to these
various outcomes in order to generate a recommendation, though that recommendation may be
merely to flip a coin.
These, then, are the four lnowledge conditions
of moral decisionmaking: we know that a decision
must be mad,e,tphen a decision must be made,
what choices are available, and,ushatis needed to
make the choice, From the Biblical "Thou shalt not
steal" and the Golden Rule, to Kant's categorical
imperative and the utilitarian injunction to achieve
the greatest good for the greatest number, the core
precepts of the major systemsof ethical thought
are directed to agents who satisfz the knowledge
conditions. If the conditions are not satisfied, ethical systemsgenerally respond with mitigation or
even immunity: forgiving those who "know not
what they do" is basic to Western understandings
of moral responsibility.
Ignorance can, ofcourse, be culpable; but most
philosophers and legal theorists who aclnowledge
the phenomenon of culpable ignorance have implicitly confined it to a small range of exceptional
casesiconspirators who attempt to preserve their
deniability, or drunks who have willfully stupefted
themselves. The possibility that the modern workplace may place millions of or&nary individuals in
a state of culpable ignorance throughout their careers has never, to our knowledge, been explicitly
addressedin moral theory.
In an organizational setting, one or more of the
four knowledge conditions tlpically fails at a critical
juncture. As the Milgram erperiments illustrated,
in&viduals in bureaucratic settings may not fully ap-
preciate that a decision must be made, understand
when it should be made, realize what choices are
open to them, and comprehend what the consequences of different choices will be. A law firm associate asked to research a small point of law or a
junior architect asked to design a detail may have
no idea that the project as a whole raisesdeep questions of professional ethics. Even if they have their
suspicions,it is often impossible to pinpoint a moment of truth when the decision must be made. No
clear list ofoptions, or even clear understanding of
who to speak with, may exist, and the subor&nate
may never believe she has sufffcient information to
fashion a solution.
The failure of these lcrowledge conditions is created or maintained by organizational structure.
Typically, supervisors parcel out subtasksto a number of subordinate employees.None of the subordinates may have more than the most general idea
of what the entire project is about, while the supervisor may know nothing about the details of each
subordinate'ssubtasks.No member of the organization might recognize a moral problem, because
the problem arises not from what anyone member
ofthe team is doing, but rather from all their actions put together. The fact that each is merely a
member of a team lulls them into a senseof security, so that they feel no pressing need to find out
more about what is going on. Though they may resolve not to be "good Germans" at the moment of
truth, the moment of truth never arrives.
This, then, is t}re central philosophical question
that the problem of fragmented knowledge raises:
Is it possible to formulate satisfac-toryprinciples of
indioidual responsibilitg when any or all of the four
knouledge conditions presupposed by standard
mnral theoriesfail?
WITHOUT
KNOWLEDGE
RESPONSIBILITY
. . . At bottom, four approachesexist to the problem of "deeds witlout doers." First, we can simply
accept as a tragic fact of modern existence&at organizational wrongs may be committed for which
no one-neither individuals nor the organizationcan rightly be held responsible. Mor:e optimistically, we can either hold the organization itself
50
PartOner MoralPhilosophy
andBusiness
We would do better to focus on the driving aspect of the drunk driving analogy.Driving is a valuable activity, and our licensing procedures are
designed to make it widely available. Because of
the lethal potential of the automobile, however, the
privilege ofdriving hinges on an exerciseofalertness,caution, and self-restraint ttrat we do not require of pedestrians or passengers.We allow pedestrians and passengersto impair their reflexes and
Extending Individual Responsibility
judgment with alcohol, but we treat it as a legal and
The simplestway of extendingthe concept of culpa- moral offense for a driver or prospective driver to
ble ignorance to situations in which the lanowledge do so.
Analogously,becauseofthe great potential for
conditions fail is to invoke an analogy to drunk driving. By the time a driver has had six drinks, he may harm arising from the division oflabor and fragno longer have the refexes or judgment to avoid an mentation of knowledge in a colporate or bureauaccident, and thus in one sensehe is not responsible cratic organization, employees may acquire duties
for what he does behind the wheel. Obviously, far more demanding than doing no evil. They must
though, we do hold him responsible.Why? The an- look and listen for evil and attempt to thwart it if
swer seemssimple enough, although we agree that t}ey &scover it. These duties, however, are not as
once he became drunk he lost effective control of limited and well-defined as those imposed on the
his actions, we blame him for becoming drrnk ln the driver. We erpect prospective drivers to "just say
first place. Though he was not fully responsible at no," but we cannot erpect organizationalemploythe time of the accident, it was his own fault that he ees to know everything about the operation in
was not responsible.In Aristode'swords, "when one which they are involved. While drinking is a gratuhas once let go of a stone, it is too late to get it itous impediment to driving, fragmented knowlback-but the agent was responsible for throwing it, edge inheres in the structure ofthe organization
because the origin of the action was in himself."la
itself. We are Ieft with a question that does not arise
Analogously,we may agree that individuals in in the context of drunk driving: What and how
organizational settings often do not know enough much precaution do we require of the individual
to be held responsible for organizational wrongdo- employee?
We cannot answer t}is question definitively, but
ings and yet we insist that they should have known.
They were willfully blind. Thus, for example, if an we can begin by suggestingseveral obligations that
SS officer claimed that he did not l
Purchase answer to see full
attachment