The Ethics of Using Performance-Enhancing Drugs
87
ery and
on the
prolonged
arteriosclerosis, serious hypertension, a lowered sperm count in males, and de-
velopment of masculine physical characteristics in women. The regular and
ted to
Coster-
imate
d not
to be taking steroids at dosages so high that it would be illegal to administer
open
chas
use of steroids is also asserted to produce such personality changes
as increased aggressiveness and hostility.
What is particularly frightening is that world-class athletes are reported
them to human subjects in legitimate medical experiments. Some athletes are
said to “stack” various forms of steroids along with other kinds of performance
enhancers
, such as human growth hormones, in attempts to find the most ef-
fective combinations. Moreover
, many, perhaps most, athletes who use steroids
do so without medical supervision. Such athletes are likely to ignore claims
that steroids have little effect on performance when such claims are based on
studies that administer only low doses of the relevant drugs.
in an
ones
gard
ssist
that
een
y to
agh
put
Evaluating the Use of Steroids sime
Various reasons are cited as justifications of the claim that competitive athletes
ought not use performance-enhancing steroids. Among the most frequently
cited are the following: (1) use of steroids to enhance performance is harmful
to athletes, who need to be protected; (2) use of steroids to enhance perfor-
mance by some athletes coerces others into using steroids; (3) use of steroids
to enhance performance is unfair or a form of cheating; (4) use of steroids to
enhance performance violates justifiable norms or ideals that ought to govern
athletic competition; and (5) use of steroids demeans or cheapens achievement
in sport, for example, by making home runs too common and too easy to hit in
baseball. Let us examine each kind of justification in turn.
ert
es
at
Paternalism, Informed Consent, and the Use of Steroids
Why shouldn't athletes be allowed to use performance-enhancing steroids?
According to one argument, steroids, particularly at the high dosages believed
necessary to enhance performance, can seriously harm those who use them. For
example
, according to the Mitchell Report, “Steroid users place themselves at
risk for psychiatric problems, cardiovascular and liver damage, drastic changes
to their reproductive systems, musculoskeletal injuries, and other problems?
The report adds that “users of human growth hormone risk cancer, harm to
reproductive health, cardiac and thyroid problems, and overgrowth of
bone and connective tissue.”? Let us accept the factual claim that steroids as
performance enhancers can be seriously harmful and consider whether poten-
tial harm to the user justifies prohibiting their use.
The principal criticism of prohibiting steroid use to protect athletes from
their
themselves is that it is unjustifiably paternalistic. Paternalistic interference
88
Chapter 4: Drugs, Genes, and Enhancing Performance in Spon
prevents athletes from making decisions for themselves. After all, would any of
spread paternalism was practiced, third parties could prohibit us from eating
that our personal decisions about how to live our lives were too risky? If wide.
foods that might be harmful, playing in sports that carried even slight risk of
injury, or indulging in unhealthy lifestyles. Our lives would be monitored for
our own good, of course. The difficulty is that we might not conceive of our
The trouble with paternalism, then, is that it restricts human liberty. We
may believe, with John Stuart Mill, the great nineteenth-century defender of hu-
man freedom, "that the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised
over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm
to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant
If each of us ought to be free to assume risks we think are worth taking,
shouldn't athletes have the same freedom? In particular, if athletes prefer
own good in the same way as the paternalist.
rational decisions?
wау.
the gains in performance the use of steroids allegedly provides, along with the
increased risk of harm, to the alternative of less risk and worse performance,
performance,
own
what gives anyone else the right to interfere with their choice? After all, if we
should not forbid smokers from risking their health by smoking, why should
we prohibit track stars, baseball players, or weight lifters from taking risks with
their health in pursuit of their goals?
Although these antipaternalistic considerations have great force, we can-
not yet dismiss paternalism as a justification for prohibiting steroids as perfor-
mance enhancers. First we must consider some difficulties with this view. Even
Mill acknowledged that the kind of antipaternalism articulated in his Harm
Principle (the principle stating that the only justification for limiting liberty is
to prevent harm to others) had limits. Mill excluded children and young peo-
ple below the age of maturity as well as those, such as the mentally ill, who may
require care from others. Moreover, Mill would surely exempt those who are
misinformed or coerced from the immediate protection of the principle. To
use one of his own examples, if you attempt to cross a bridge in the dark, not
knowing that the bridge has been washed away by a flood, I do not violate the
Harm Principle by preventing you from attempting the crossing until I have
explained the situation to you.'
In particular, before accepting the antipaternalistic argument, we need to
decide whether athletes who use steroids to enhance performance really are
making a free and informed choice. If behavior is not the result of free and
informed choice, it is not really the action of a rational autonomous agent. If
it is not informed, the person does not truly know what she is doing, but if the
behavior is coerced, it is not what the agent wants to do in the first place.
The Ethics of Using Performance-Enhancing Drugs 89
Is there reason to believe athletes who use steroids are either uninformed
about the effects of the drug or are coerced or otherwise incompetent to make
First, those below the age of consent can legitimately be prevented on pa-
behavior, even if the children want to take their chances on getting hurt, so
that parents can prevent children from engaging in potentially harmful
prohibit the use of harmful performance enhancers by
sports authorities can
against possible benefits due to their youth.
those who are less capable of accurately weighing risks and potential harms
Moreover, elite athletes often are role models for younger athletes, who
may strive to imitate their idols or hope to eventually achieve similar levels of
performance-enhancing drugs to better their
success. When elite athletes use
their use may encourage minors, whose reasoning capabil-
points out, even if steroid use by high school athletes is declining, as has been
ities have not yet fully developed, to use them as well. As the Mitchell Report
reported, and only 3 to 6 percent of such young people are using steroids, it
such drugs. 1° Therefore, instead of trying to justify restrictions on the use of
still would be the case that hundreds of thousands of young people are using
performance-enhancing drugs by appealing to paternalism toward competent
adult athletes, we can justify the restrictions with the claim that we must fulfill
hend the short-term and long-term risks involved in steroid use, from them-
our duty to protect younger athletes, who often cannot completely compre-
selves. One point that could be raised here is that, although young athletes may
be negatively influenced by the examples of athletes who use steroids and other
illegal performance enhancers, they may also be dissuaded from using such
substances by high-profile cases of those athletes caught and sanctioned for us-
ing them. The fall from grace of American cycling icon Lance Armstrong, for
example, provides a cautionary tale of how using illegal enhancers can destroy
athlete's career and legacy. It could be argued that such examples serve to
persuade young athletes that illegal performance enhancers should not be used
in their pursuit of excellence and advancement in
A second possible problem with the role model argument is that it is not
sport.
completely consistent with our practices in other areas. We don't prevent adults
from consuming alcohol, for example, even though adult drinkers may serve
as models for alcohol abuse by underage drinkers. Adults normally are not
prohibited by law from being bad role models for young people. Why should
we apply a double standard to athletes? The above points suggest that although
we cannot ignore the effects of star adult athletes' steroid use on young peo-
ple
, the claim that prohibitions on competent athletes' use of performance
an
90
91
of the argument.
sent to
skeptical
pres-
Chapter 4: Drugs, Genes, and Enhancing Performance in Sport
less competent individuals is dubious. Such a consideration may factor into the
enhancers can be justified solely on the basis of the need to protect younger,
ultimate case against allowing steroid use, but it cannot bear the whole weight
The Ethics of Using Performance-Enhancing Drugs
steroids adequately informed about the serious potential side effects of these
What about the requirement of informed consent? Are athletes who use
writer concluded, "the onus is on the athlete to continue playing and to con-
about the information available, but it is hard to believe that most adult us-
drugs? Some athletes, particularly teenagers, may be uninformed or s
subtle, makes the athlete vulnerable. It also takes away the athlete's ability to act
things he or she would not otherwise consent to.... Coercion, however
ers of steroids could be ignorant of the risks involved. Even if H. L. Mencken
and choose freely with regard to informed consent.” 11
Although this point may not be without force in specific contexts, the use
may not have been totally off the mark when he suggested it was impossible
to go broke by underestimating the intelligence of the American people, it is
it makes of the term "coercion” seems questionable. After all, no one literally is
forced to become (or remain) a professional athlete or to participate at elite levels
difficult to believe, in view of the amount of publicity devoted to the use of
in amateur athletics. If we want to use "coercion” so broadly, are we also com-
performance enhancers, that the majority of mature athletes could be unaware
mitted, absurdly it seems, to saying that coaches coerce players into practicing or
that steroid use can be dangerous. However, even if ignorance about the effects
it more plausible to say that although there are pressures on athletes to achieve
training hard? Do professors similarly coerce students into studying hard? Isn't
peak physical condition, these no more amount to coercion than do the
sures on law or medical students to study hard. Rather, the athletes (or the stu-
dents) have reasons to try hard to achieve success; the pressures are self-imposed.
n freely decide that the gains of steroid use outweigh the risks. Surely we are
At best it is unclear whether top athletes are coerced into using steroids or
not entitled to assume that professional athletes as a class are unable to give in-
formed consent to steroid use unless we are willing to count similar pressures
in other professions as forms of coercion as well. And if we use "coercion” that
broadly, it becomes unclear who, if anybody, is left free.
Sometimes, however, in particular contexts athletes may be victims of co-
some of Lance Armstrong's teammates alleged that he
pressured them to use illegal performance enhancers. With the power he ac-
crued over time as seven-time Tour de France winner, such pressure could be
perceived as coercion, as it seems that refusal to dope could have resulted in a
cyclists dismissal from the team; specific overt or even implied threats do im-
ply coercion. Apart from such specific situations, however
, it appears doubtful
that the athlete's general desire to be successful at his or her profession can by
itself undermine the capacity for free choice.
But is this conclusion too hasty? A critic might point out that even if the
athlete's own internal desires for success do not rule out free choice, coercion
from other competitors could be present. That is, even if we agree that inter-
Coercion and Freedom in Sports
nal pressures generated by the athletes are not coercive, we might suspect that
What about the requirement of free choice? Are athletes really free to not use
their competitors create external pressures that are. It is sometimes argued
steroids? At least some analysts would argue that athletes are coerced into us-
that even if some sophisticated athletes do give informed consent, their drug
ing steroids. Consider professional sports. The professional athlete's livelihood
use may force others into taking steroids as well. Athletes who would prefer
may depend on performing at the highest level. Athletes who are not
not to become users may believe that unless they take the drugs, they will not
the best in the world may not be professionals for very long. Thus, as one
be able to compete with those who do. Athletes may believe they are trapped
because they are faced with a choice in which neither option is attractive. don't
lake steroids and lose, or take them and remain competitive.
ercion. For example,
of steroids were widespread, antipaternalists still might argue that fostering
informed choice through improved drug education is a better remedy than
simple prohibition
Accordingly, paternalism alone probably does not provide a strong enough
justification for prohibiting competent athletes' use of harmful performance-
enhancing drugs, although it does justify prohibiting those below the age of
consent from using them. However, we should leave open the possibility that
paternalism, when conjoined with other premises, may provide partial support
for prohibition. For example, if steroid use by some people reasonably may be
thought to threaten harm to others as well as to the users, and if it is less clear
than suggested above that adult users give free consent to assuming the risk
of use, then a limited kind of paternalism may play a supporting role in the
prohibitionist argument. The argument for prohibiting steroids might then
be similar to the argument for requiring automobile drivers to wear seatbelts:
we may justifiably require automobile drivers to wear seatbelts because it is
for their own protection, because the decision not to buckle up may not re-
sult from thoughtful consideration of the dangers involved, and because of the
high costs associated with collisions, which place a burden on the health care
dias
system as well as the taxpayers who support it.
o visto que
among
93
but only to prevent harm to others.
nosni
open
the term "coercion."
ing
contribution.
Note that the argument here is no longer that we should interfere with
ter 4: Drugs, Genes, and Enhancing Performance in Sport
but that we should interfere with them to prevent them from coercing others.
athletes on paternalistic grounds-to prevent them from harming themselves
Such an argument is in accord with Mill's Harm Principle: liberty is restricted
The Ethics of Using Performance-Enhancing Drugs
into using performance enhancers too? One reason for doubting they do is
Do pressures generated by athletes who use drugs coerce other athletes
Unethically Constrained Choice
that it once again appears as if "coercion” is being used too broadly. One might
The appeal to coercion as a justification for prohibiting the use of steroids is
just as well say that students who study harder than others "coerce" their class
7 to the charge that it uses the notion of coercion far too broadly. Perhaps
mates into studying harder in order to keep up or that athletes who practice
the argument can be reconstructed or modified without unacceptably stretch-
Whatever the proper definition of coercion, what seems to make coer-
longer hours than others "coerce" their competitors into practicing longer
hours as well. The problem with such claims is that all competitive pressure
improperly interferes with the freedom of another. Thus, if we are reluctant to
cion presumptively wrong is that it unduly, illegitimately, or in some other way
becomes "coercive." As a result, the term "coercion” is deprived of any moral
force. Indeed, if all the competitive behaviors that were "coercive" in this way
harder than her competitors is coercing them, perhaps it is because we do not
say that the student who studies harder than his peers or the athlete who trains
think the student or the athlete is acting improperly to begin with. Both have
a right to work harder, so their working harder does not coerce others to do
have no reason to prohibit the behavior of the student or the athlete (and even
have reason to encourage it because it leads to superior achievement). In fact,
their hard work may be inspiring to others and thus make a positive social
But consider another situation in which competitive pressures are im-
posed improperly. Suppose you work in a firm where young employees com-
e for promotions to higher levels. Up to a point, if some work harder than
others, no ethical issue is involved, because it is not wrong and usually highly
desirable for some workers to try to perform better than others. But now sup-
pose that some workers work all the time, including weekends. Everyone feels
the pressure to keep up, and soon all the workers give up their holidays and
evenings for fear they will lose their jobs if they do not. In this situation it is
more plausible to conclude that the workers are coerced or, if not “coerced.”
then at least unjustifiably pressured into putting in many hours of overtime.
Let us go further. Suppose some of the workers start taking stimulants-
drugs having harmful side effects-so they can work even harder. Other
defended.
workers feel that to keep up they too must take the stimulants. They ask the
But before any such argument can be made good, we need to consider
employer to set limits on the amount of time they are expected to work be-
whether steroid users do have a right to impose the choice of becoming a user
cause they are being coerced into taking the stimulant to keep their jobs.
on others. And even if they have such a right, would it be wrong for them
In this example it is unclear whether the workers who take the stimulants
to exercise it? Rather than engaging in a conceptual analysis of the notion of
are behaving properly. Arguably, they are putting undue pressure on other
"coercion," perhaps it will be more profitable to consider directly whether it is
workers to risk harming themselves so they can keep their jobs. If so, the work-
morally wrong for athletes who use steroids to place other athletes in a situ- ers taking the stimulants are violating the freedom of their fellow workers, and
tion in which they must choose between becoming users themselves or be- their behavior may be regulated in the interests of protecting the freedom of all.
Is the practice of steroid use in competitive sports like that of our last exam-
oming competitively disadvantaged.
be
sed
berabit
isins be dition to our
were put into a list, virtually no competitive behaviors would be left over that
were not coercive.
Critics might reply that there is a difference between weight training and
extra studying, on one hand, and steroid use, on the other. As one writer has
pointed out, “Steroids place regard for enhancement of athletic performance
above regard for the health of the athletes themselves.” 12 Weight training
should make athletes stronger and more resistant to injury; studying normally
enhances the intellectual ability of students. But steroid use, even if it enhances
athletic performance, also presents serious risk of harm to the user.
These differences are important and suggest that the use of steroids does
present athletes with a difficult choice. But is this enough to show that a user
coerces other athletes into also becoming users? Much depends upon how
we understand the term “coercion.” 13 If we understand coercion to mean im-
posing difficult choices on others when we have no right to do so and if we
assume the user has no right to impose the choice of using or not using on
other athletes, then perhaps a strong form of the coercion argument can be
pete
ple
? Do users of dangerous performance-enhancing drugs behave improperly
94
95
withdraw." 14
Chapter 4: Drugs, Genes, and Enhancing Performance in Sport
when they put pressure on others to keep up competitively? Some would
"No!” As one writer has argued, "the ingestion of steroids for competitive
into world class competition. ... If they find the costs excessive, they may
to which athletes subject themselves to achieve success. No one is coerced
sons cannot be distinguished from the other tortures, deprivations, and risks
The Ethics of Using Performance-Enhancing Drugs
Although such a rejoinder has force, it may not be decisive. Although
steroid use is not strictly "coercive" because athletes can always withdraw from
the competition, the choice of either using a potentially harmful drug or being
consider the effects of elite athletes using steroids on impressionable young
athletes as an added reinforcing factor (the "role model" argument is discussed
noncompetitive may be unethical if it is imposed on others. Perhaps a pro-
more fully in Chapter 8). Perhaps this presumption can be strengthened when
conjoined with another argument of a different but not totally unrelated kind.
hibition on steroids can be justified as a means of protecting athletes from
being placed in a position in which they have to make such a choice. To the
Fairness, Cheating, and the Use of Performance Enhancers
extent that we think it is wrong or illegitimate to present athletes with such a
Many of those who object to the use of performance-enhancing drugs in sport
dilemma, then to that extent we will find the argument from coercion to have
do so not (or not only) because they believe users coerce others into using
reasons, if any, can be given for regarding the use of drugs such as steroids as
these drugs but (also) because they believe that such use is cheating. What
an unfair competitive practice?
their opponents are doing more than claiming that users are breaking existing
rules. For instance, many fans of Major League Baseball claim that players who
used steroids and other performance enhancers before the explicit prohibition
Of course, if the existing rules prohibit the use of such drugs, then their
use is cheating. Those who secretly violate the rules take unfair advantage of
those who don't. The interesting philosophical issue is whether sports organi-
zations should adopt the rules prohibiting the use of performance-enhancing
of their use prior to the 2004 season were cheating. 15
drugs in the first place, or if such rules already exist, they should be changed
to allow the use of performance-enhancing drugs. Would allowing the use of
performance-enhancing drugs be unfair even if such drugs were available to
a point. Regardless of whether we want to apply the term “coercion" in such
a context, we need to consider whether it is morally wrong to insist that ath.
letes risk harming themselves to compete. If so, a prohibition on steroid use
may be justified as a means of protecting athletes against having such a choice
imposed upon them and protecting them from competitive pressures that, if
unregulated, are far too likely to get out of hand.
Such considerations may not satisfy those who think steroid use is
per-
missible. They would reply that athletes are not considered unethical if they
engage in demanding training and thereby impose hard choices on other com-
petitors. How can we justifiably condemn the users of performance-enhancing
drugs for confronting competitors with difficult choices when we do not make
the same judgment in similar situations?
This rejoinder does need to be explored further, but it is far from deci-
sive. Perhaps we can distinguish the risks inherent in stressful training pro-
grams from those inherent in the use of steroids. As M. Andrew Holowchak
remarked in a passage quoted earlier, we might distinguish between steroid
use, which can be harmful, and training, which, if done properly, promotes
conditioning and reduces the chances of injury.
pro-
Although we have not arrived at an uncontroversial justification for
hibiting the use of steroids in organized athletic competition, we have discov-
ered an argument that is well worth further examination. According to this
argument, athletes who use steroids have no right to put other athletes in the
position of either damaging their health or competing under a significant dis-
all participants in a sport?
Many of us share the feeling that use of performance enhancers provides
an unfair advantage, but we need to ask whether there are good arguments
to support this intuitive conclusion. We also need to consider just where the
unfairness lies. Roger Gardner made a perceptive distinction when he asked
whether steroid use was unfair to competitors because of the advantage it
provides or was unfair to the game because it made success too easy. It will
be useful to keep this distinction in mind as we explore the topic further in
what follows. 16
One line of argument suggests an analogy with differences in the equip-
ment available to competitors. For example, if one player in a golf tourna-
ment used golf balls that went significantly farther than balls opponents
used, even when struck with the same force, and the same ball was avail-
able for others to use, the tournament arguably would be unfair. One player
would be able to avoid one of the major challenges of golf not through skill
but by using a superior product
. Perhaps the use of steroids provides a sim-
advantage. Whether it will survive the test of further critical discussion remains
to be seen, but perhaps it is strong enough to create at least a presumption in
favor of prohibiting steroids in athletic competition, especially when we also
ilar unfair advantage.
Purchase answer to see full
attachment