Respond to peers, philosophy homework help

Anonymous

Question Description

This is a peer response. The intent is to further the discussion by examining their claims or argument. If you agree with the students post, then explain why, if not, also ensure to explain why and provide evidence of why you disagree. You may ask the student questions as well, but ensure it is targeted on the subject. There are three students to respond to. Each response must be at least 150 words and must have 1 in text citation from the reading material provided.

Unformatted Attachment Preview

Initial Discussion Instructions: One famous worry about utilitarianism is that it demands that we regard our own set of desires, ends, and our own happiness, as just one among a great many others whose lives we might impact. Accordingly, our own desires, ends, etc. bear very little weight when determining what the greatest happiness of the greatest numberis, and thus what our moral responsibility is. Think of a situation or area of life in which this might be true, and our concern for our own well-being and happiness has to take a back seat to the concern for the wellbeing and happiness of the greatest number. What might a utilitarian say to someone who thinks this is too high a sacrifice? Would this be a plausible response? Be sure to back up your answer with references to the resources, and respond to your peers by considering what someone who disagrees with them might say. Response to peers Instructions: Reply to your classmates and instructor. Try to attempt to take the conversation further by examining their claims or arguments in more depth or responding to the posts that they make to you. Keep the discussion on target and try to analyze things in as much detail as you can. You must utilize the reading material as a reference and ensure the reference is in APA style. Student 1: Utilitarianism is an ethical doctrine that merits based on utility where behavior should be aspired at bringing happiness to the utmost number of individuals. Mosser (2013) emphasizes that many of us find utilitarianism as a simple and beneficial approach when it comes to making ethical judgements. An action is deliberated as right if it guides to happiness and wrong if it guides to pain. A great example of utilitarianism is the rule that would permit medical physicians to kill healthy individuals to utilize their organs for transplants that will save the lives of many other individuals who would otherwise pass away without such organs. If a physician is able to save five individuals from deceasing by killing one healthy individual, then utilitarianism suggests that the physician should kill one individual to save the lives of five other individuals. A very usual argument in contradiction to act utilitarianism is that it has the tendency to give incorrect answers to moral questions. Critics discuss that it permits some actions that every person thinks and knows that are unethical, for instance the case above. For example, in the case above, physicians would be violating the law by killing one such individual. Correspondingly, individuals would not belief in physicians in the concern that they could be prospective victims for such organs and would fear acts like for example: a surgical operation. Sheskin, & Baumard (2016) state that individuals usually show non-utilitarian judgments in different areas like for example: healthcare choices, income distributions, and disciplinary laws. Utilitarian discusses that the overall good of a deed should be taken into thought. Therefore, an act that produces the greatest number of utility should be attained. Student 2: According to Bentham, utility is what others are able to gain as a result of the hard work that we put in our day to day life (Mosser, 2013). One area in life where this might be true is in the family set up. A father and a mother who are involved in a relationship go through the greatest lengths to just see to it that their sons are satisfied before they even fulfill their own needs. For example, when a kid is small and they start crying, the father or mother will drop what they are doing to just make sure that their kids are back to sleep and that they are okay. This will be regardless of whether they are tired or they are not tired, they will do their best to ensure that their kids are safely back to the position where they were before and that they are not crying again. In this situation we observe that the parents sacrifice their own happiness for the happiness of their children. The parents choosing to forego their sleep or the work that they were doing, which if they would have concentrated on it more, they would have gained from it just so that they can be able to assist their kids out of the discomforts that they are having. The utilitarianism idea is complete when the child is able to stop crying or being in discomfort as a result of the actions of their parents. What a utilitarian would say to someone who thinks this too high a sacrifice. The opinion of a utilitarian would be that the satisfaction that is derived when one does such a selfless act to be able to calm the other person down is far much greater than the act that a person would have done for themselves which would mean that they forego those of the other people (Mori, 2015). For example. for a utilitarian the satisfaction these parents gets when they wake up to attend to their child is that the child might have wet the bed and the urine might be burning their skin. If the parent ignores their cry and the child cries himself to sleep, what happens is that the child might get a rash lying in the wet bed. This will incur additional costs to the parents which will require them to take their children to the hospital for medical attention. If the parents had woken up, all they would have lost was sleep which they could get later because sleep is free. In this sense the parents will have prevented themselves from using additional amounts money for medical treatment for their child. Would this be a plausible response? This in all sense is reasonable plausible because saving oneself from additional costs is what is considered economical and that is what utilitarianism is all about, "the act should produce the greatest net good, or the greatest amount of happiness, for the greatest number" (Mosser, 2013). Student 3: I think one area in which utilitarianism is present would be in the area of criminal justice. For example, let's say we have a murderer (first-degree). The family of the victim is more than likely going to want to see the perpetrator killed as well, wanting "justice" for their family member. I mean, how harshly should a criminal be punished or corrected? Utilitarianism brings several ideas to the table. First, criminals are still human beings, not matter how violent or the crime, and deserve moral consideration. We should "punish" them as leniently as possible, but punishing them can prevent future harm, so we should consider different types of sentencing as a deterrent, such as paying for damages or working in community service. This can help some of the harm done by the crime to be taken away. I think utilitarianism ushers in a new kind of light on many situations. Instead of everyone getting what it is they want, there must be sacrifice to support the greater good for everyone involved, whether directly or indirectly. Utilitarianism helps us think and realize that criminals can be rehabilitated and molded into highly functioning members of society. Perhaps the most notable aspect that utilitarianism rejects is, retaliation. Utilitarianism rejects the traditional narrative that bad people deserve to have bad things done to them. Instead it focuses on what future good punishment can do and provide. I think a utilitarian would tell someone who thinks most criminals should (I apologize for the use of wording, but have nothing else) be shot and killed because it would be cheaper and easier, that their way of thinking is flawed. That killing criminals would be too detrimental to society and would not help the greater good, but help those get the retaliation we mentioned above. They would say, who would be the judge of what qualifies as a crime bad enough or violent enough for someone to just be killed? As Winston Churchill once said, "If you kill the murderer, the quantity of murderers will not change" (Churchill, 1940s). In my opinion, I think the above possible response by a utilitarian would be plausible, because their argument against killing every criminal intends to show the person that it is ethically unacceptable to kill all criminals, as well as show them why they are wanting them dead in the first place, retaliation. Overall, Utilitarianism intends to reveal what is morally and ethically right or wrong based on the effects every action would leave behind. Utilitarians believe that the purpose of morality is to make life better by increasing the amount of good things (such as pleasure and happiness) in the world and decreasing the amount of bad things (such as pain and unhappiness). They reject moral codes or systems that consist of commands or taboos that are based on customs, traditions, or orders given by leaders or supernatural beings. Instead, utilitarians think that what makes a morality be true or justifiable is its positive contribution to human (and perhaps non-human) beings. (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2017). This being the case, we can see how the above examples using the criminal justice system would be unethical through the eyes of Utilitarianism. 61 Traditional of Ethics IntroducingTheories Philosophy Federico©Terry Caputo/iStock/Thinkstock Why/ Getty Images You have your way. I have my way. As for “It is the mark of an educated mind the right way, the correct way, and the only to be able to entertain a thought way, it does not exist. without accepting it” —Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra —Aristotle mos81165_06_c06.indd 175 1/6/14 2:33 PM CHAPTER 6 Section 6.1 How Should One Act? Learning Objectives After reading this chapter, students will be able to: 1. Characterize the classical theories of ethics—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics. 2. Identify some of the problems these theories confront. 3. Describe other metaethical views, such as relativism and egoism. 4. Apply ethical theories to problems that affect both individuals and larger groups, including environmental challenges. What We Will Discover • Philosophers have developed theories to provide support for our claims about right and wrong. • Other theories such as egoism and relativism offer alternatives to traditional theories of ethics. • Ethics has many specific applications to our lives, from the very personal and specific to those that affect everyone in society. 6.1 How Should One Act? E thics, or moral philosophy, investigates how we can evaluate our behavior in terms of right and wrong, good and bad—in other words, how we determine what we should do, what we should not do, and how to tell the difference. After looking at the three classical ethical views that philosophers have presented and some of the problems with these theories, we will explore some alternative approaches. Utilitarianism Suppose you and five of your friends are hanging out one night and decide to order a pizza. You are all equally hungry and decide to order two pizzas, each of which has six slices. Thus, when the pizzas are delivered, it is pretty easy to determine how to divide the pizzas in a way that is the fairest: Everyone gets two slices. It may be that one person wanted a third slice, and someone else may have only wanted one. Yet without knowing anything else, this arrangement, more than any other, will be the most beneficial to the greatest number of people. Photos.com/© Getty Images/Thinkstock Jeremy Bentham is associated with the founding of utilitarianism, which states that given a choice between two acts, the one that creates greater happiness for the greatest number of people should be chosen. This simple example demonstrates the basic notion at the heart of the ethical doctrine known as utilitarianism. Often associated with the philosophers Jeremy Bentham (1748–1822) and John Stuart Mill, utilitarianism offers a very straightforward and direct way to evaluate behavior. When given a choice between two acts, utilitarianism states that mos81165_06_c06.indd 176 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 the act that should be chosen is the one that creates the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of people. Philosophers (and economists) often use the term utility to express this quality. Utility is the satisfaction one gets from something. For instance, if you like chocolate ice cream more than vanilla ice cream, we can say that chocolate ice cream has a higher utility for you, relative to vanilla ice cream. In theory, at least, each of us can rank all of our choices according to a scale that indicates our relative preferences. Some philosophers, such as Bentham, even attempted to assign numbers to these preferences. If someone likes chocolate ice cream five times as much as vanilla ice cream, that person would presumably be willing to accept five vanilla ice cream cones as a substitute for one chocolate ice cream cone. It should also be noted that utility is regarded in terms of net utility: The correct moral choice is that which generates the greatest good and also minimizes unhappiness. Read more of John Stuart Mill’s ideas on this topic in his work Utilitarianism in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. Because utilitarianism considers an act’s consequences in assessing its morality, utilitarianism is also regarded as a consequentialist theory. The basic idea in consequentialism is to consider the consequences that will result from the choices one confronts: If the consequences of one act produce the greatest net good—or the highest utility—for the greatest number of people, this is the act one should carry out. Many people find this to be a rather obvious ethical viewpoint; clearly if we had decided to give all the pizza slices to just three people and no slices to the other three, this would seem rather unfair. It should also be clear that utilitarianism offers an approach to scenarios other than distributing pizza and ice cream. Imagine Mary really loves to dance, but she does not get to go dancing very often. Mary has three children, with whom she enjoys spending time and who enjoy spending time with her. One night she is given the option of staying home and spending time with her children or going dancing. What should she do? The utilitarian might argue that, on the one hand, the pleasure Mary gets from dancing is greater than staying with her children. Yet on the other hand, her children will receive great pleasure if she does not go dancing. Therefore, the “utility calculation” is that the net happiness of Mary and her three children will be higher if she stays home, even though Mary’s individual happiness might be slightly lower than it would have been if she had chosen to go dancing. Utility is often described in terms of pleasure, which can be problematic for utilitarianism. Imagine someone finds pleasure in playing video games and drinking beer all day long. Given a choice between, say, helping out in a homeless shelter or drinking and playing the newest video game, a person may well choose the latter, which suggests to some that utilitarianism has no way to distinguish between different kinds of pleasures. Presumably, we want our theory to be able to make a distinction between hedonistic and nobler pleasures. Mill saw this as a potential problem and insisted that pleasure should be considered not just in terms of quantity but also quality: that certain kinds of pleasures, or certain ways of satisfying desires, are simply better than others. A pig may be happy rolling around in the mud and eating garbage, but Mill insisted that people who take that approach to pleasure fail to develop their potential as human beings (relative to pigs, at least). According to Mill, it is better to be a dissatisfied Socrates than a satisfied pig. This is not to say that one should always choose something less pleasurable; rather, it is simply an indication that pleasures themselves can, or perhaps should, be distinguished from each other. It is not always easy to say that one pleasure is “superior” to another, and certainly people have long argued about this issue. However, these kinds of examples indicate a problem utilitarianism confronts if we evaluate acts solely in terms of their pleasurable consequences (Mill, 1909). mos81165_06_c06.indd 177 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Many people find utilitarianism to be an easy and useful approach to making ethical decisions. When distributing goods, services, or even time, it would seem to be a “no-brainer” to choose the option that would satisfy or please as many people as possible, compared to any other available choice. However, philosophers have raised a number of problems in response to utilitarianism, which may make it a less plausible ethical theory than it first appears. Problems With Utilitarianism Utilitarianism has what philosophers call an intuitive appeal: It seems to be relatively obvious, and just plain common sense, to evaluate our actions based on the results those actions produce. If all we know about a situation is that four kids in a sandbox have one toy, the best option would be for the children to share that toy, even if each child is quite sure he or she would get the most pleasure from playing with it alone. However, many philosophers have objected to utilitarianism, and for a number of reasons. As we have seen, distinguishing different kinds of pleasures from each other can be difficult. Does utilitarianism have any way to address the situation of a person who gets pleasure from staring at the wall or doing something else that most people would find quite unpleasant (something often called masochism)? Mill (1863) suggests there are “higher” or “more refined” pleasures and that they should be preferred, but who is to say which is a “higher” pleasure? Is reading poetry somehow better than watching soap operas? What if someone gains pleasure by sleeping all the time or hitting his thumb over and over with a hammer? More significant objections to utilitarianism have been posed on the basis of calculating the outcome, or consequences, of a choice. Suppose you are on a cruise ship that catches fire; you and 19 others are lucky enough to survive on a lifeboat. There is enough water to last for a week or more, but you have no food and do not know whether you will be rescued. Everyone is aware of how grim the future looks; as the boat drifts, everyone gets hungrier. It becomes apparent that everyone is going to die unless your group finds food. The utilitarian in the group poses the following options: All 20 people die, or 19 people live if one person is killed and eaten! To justify his position, he cites historical examples of similar cases in which cannibalism helped the majority survive. However, while this scenario may appear to result in the greatest good for the greatest number, do we really want an ethical theory that not only allows cannibalism, but actually endorses it as the fairest and most ethical decision? Few of us are likely to experience a situation this extreme, but we may find ourselves in situations where the basic utilitarian calculation actually leads to results that are very unfair and unjust. This is particularly threatening anytime individuals find themselves in a minority, whether because of their sex, race, ethnicity, religion, sexual orientation, or any of the other ways in which society categorizes people. For example, suppose a local grade school must decide if it should use taxpayer money to build ramps to make the building accessible to students in wheelchairs. This tax will likely decrease the pleasure of each taxpayer and may only be used by a few individuals throughout the year. In this way it would result in a net utility that would favor a decision not to build the ramps. Would you consider this a fair outcome? mos81165_06_c06.indd 178 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Great Ideas: The Trolley Problem A very famous challenge to our e ...
Purchase answer to see full attachment

Tutor Answer

TRUESTTutor
School: New York University

Attached.

Application of Utilitarianism - Outline
I) Response to First Student’s Post
II) Response to Second Student’s Post
III) Response to Third Student’s Post.


Running head: APPLICATION OF UTILITARIANISM - RESPONSE

Application Of Utilitarianism – Response
Name
Institution

1

APPLICATION OF UTILITARIANISM – RESPONSE

2

Application Of Utilitarianism – Response
Student 1:
The student talks about the situation of a doctor killing a patient who has very few
chances of surviving a condition he or she is in but still has healthy body organs that can be
used to save several other people who need them. This is a great example of utilitarianism
since it considers th...

flag Report DMCA
Review

Anonymous
The tutor was pretty knowledgeable, efficient and polite. Great service!

Anonymous
Heard about Studypool for a while and finally tried it. Glad I did caus this was really helpful.

Anonymous
Just what I needed… fantastic!

Studypool
4.7
Trustpilot
4.5
Sitejabber
4.4
Similar Questions
Related Tags

Brown University





1271 Tutors

California Institute of Technology




2131 Tutors

Carnegie Mellon University




982 Tutors

Columbia University





1256 Tutors

Dartmouth University





2113 Tutors

Emory University





2279 Tutors

Harvard University





599 Tutors

Massachusetts Institute of Technology



2319 Tutors

New York University





1645 Tutors

Notre Dam University





1911 Tutors

Oklahoma University





2122 Tutors

Pennsylvania State University





932 Tutors

Princeton University





1211 Tutors

Stanford University





983 Tutors

University of California





1282 Tutors

Oxford University





123 Tutors

Yale University





2325 Tutors