Classics in the History of Psychology
An internet resource developed by
Christopher D. Green
York University, Toronto, Ontario
ISSN 1492-3713
(Return to Classics index)
A Theory of Human Motivation
A. H. Maslow (1943)
Originally Published in Psychological Review, 50, 370-396.
Posted August 2000
[p. 370] I. INTRODUCTION
In a previous paper (13) various propositions were presented which would have to be
included in any theory of human motivation that could lay claim to being definitive.
These conclusions may be briefly summarized as follows:
1. The integrated wholeness of the organism must be one of the foundation stones of
motivation theory.
2. The hunger drive (or any other physiological drive) was rejected as a centering
point or model for a definitive theory of motivation. Any drive that is somatically
based and localizable was shown to be atypical rather than typical in human
motivation.
3. Such a theory should stress and center itself upon ultimate or basic goals rather than
partial or superficial ones, upon ends rather than means to these ends. Such a stress
would imply a more central place for unconscious than for conscious motivations.
4. There are usually available various cultural paths to the same goal. Therefore
conscious, specific, local-cultural desires are not as fundamental in motivation theory
as the more basic, unconscious goals.
5. Any motivated behavior, either preparatory or consummatory, must be understood
to be a channel through which many basic needs may be simultaneously expressed or
satisfied. Typically an act has more than one motivation.
6. Practically all organismic states are to be understood as motivated and as
motivating.
7. Human needs arrange themselves in hierarchies of pre-potency. That is to say, the
appearance of one need usually rests on the prior satisfaction of another, more prepotent need. Man is a perpetually wanting animal. Also no need or drive can be
treated as if it were isolated or discrete; every drive is related to the state of
satisfaction or dissatisfaction of other drives.
8. Lists of drives will get us nowhere for various theoretical and practical reasons.
Furthermore any classification of motivations [p. 371] must deal with the problem of
levels of specificity or generalization the motives to be classified.
9. Classifications of motivations must be based upon goals rather than upon
instigating drives or motivated behavior.
10. Motivation theory should be human-centered rather than animal-centered.
11. The situation or the field in which the organism reacts must be taken into account
but the field alone can rarely serve as an exclusive explanation for behavior.
Furthermore the field itself must be interpreted in terms of the organism. Field theory
cannot be a substitute for motivation theory.
12. Not only the integration of the organism must be taken into account, but also the
possibility of isolated, specific, partial or segmental reactions. It has since become
necessary to add to these another affirmation.
13. Motivation theory is not synonymous with behavior theory. The motivations are
only one class of determinants of behavior. While behavior is almost always
motivated, it is also almost always biologically, culturally and situationally
determined as well.
The present paper is an attempt to formulate a positive theory of motivation which
will satisfy these theoretical demands and at the same time conform to the known
facts, clinical and observational as well as experimental. It derives most directly,
however, from clinical experience. This theory is, I think, in the functionalist tradition
of James and Dewey, and is fused with the holism of Wertheimer (19), Goldstein (6),
and Gestalt Psychology, and with the dynamicism of Freud (4) and Adler (1). This
fusion or synthesis may arbitrarily be called a 'general-dynamic' theory.
It is far easier to perceive and to criticize the aspects in motivation theory than to
remedy them. Mostly this is because of the very serious lack of sound data in this
area. I conceive this lack of sound facts to be due primarily to the absence of a valid
theory of motivation. The present theory then must be considered to be a suggested
program or framework for future research and must stand or fall, not so much on facts
available or evidence presented, as upon researches to be done, researches suggested
perhaps, by the questions raised in this paper.[p. 372]
II. THE BASIC NEEDS
The 'physiological' needs. -- The needs that are usually taken as the starting point for
motivation theory are the so-called physiological drives. Two recent lines of research
make it necessary to revise our customary notions about these needs, first, the
development of the concept of homeostasis, and second, the finding that appetites
(preferential choices among foods) are a fairly efficient indication of actual needs or
lacks in the body.
Homeostasis refers to the body's automatic efforts to maintain a constant, normal state
of the blood stream. Cannon (2) has described this process for (1) the water content of
the blood, (2) salt content, (3) sugar content, (4) protein content, (5) fat content, (6)
calcium content, (7) oxygen content, (8) constant hydrogen-ion level (acid-base
balance) and (9) constant temperature of the blood. Obviously this list can be
extended to include other minerals, the hormones, vitamins, etc.
Young in a recent article (21) has summarized the work on appetite in its relation to
body needs. If the body lacks some chemical, the individual will tend to develop a
specific appetite or partial hunger for that food element.
Thus it seems impossible as well as useless to make any list of fundamental
physiological needs for they can come to almost any number one might wish,
depending on the degree of specificity of description. We can not identify all
physiological needs as homeostatic. That sexual desire, sleepiness, sheer activity and
maternal behavior in animals, are homeostatic, has not yet been demonstrated.
Furthermore, this list would not include the various sensory pleasures (tastes, smells,
tickling, stroking) which are probably physiological and which may become the goals
of motivated behavior.
In a previous paper (13) it has been pointed out that these physiological drives or
needs are to be considered unusual rather than typical because they are isolable, and
because they are localizable somatically. That is to say, they are relatively
independent of each other, of other motivations [p. 373] and of the organism as a
whole, and secondly, in many cases, it is possible to demonstrate a localized,
underlying somatic base for the drive. This is true less generally than has been thought
(exceptions are fatigue, sleepiness, maternal responses) but it is still true in the classic
instances of hunger, sex, and thirst.
It should be pointed out again that any of the physiological needs and the
consummatory behavior involved with them serve as channels for all sorts of other
needs as well. That is to say, the person who thinks he is hungry may actually be
seeking more for comfort, or dependence, than for vitamins or proteins. Conversely, it
is possible to satisfy the hunger need in part by other activities such as drinking water
or smoking cigarettes. In other words, relatively isolable as these physiological needs
are, they are not completely so.
Undoubtedly these physiological needs are the most pre-potent of all needs. What this
means specifically is, that in the human being who is missing everything in life in an
extreme fashion, it is most likely that the major motivation would be the physiological
needs rather than any others. A person who is lacking food, safety, love, and esteem
would most probably hunger for food more strongly than for anything else.
If all the needs are unsatisfied, and the organism is then dominated by the
physiological needs, all other needs may become simply non-existent or be pushed
into the background. It is then fair to characterize the whole organism by saying
simply that it is hungry, for consciousness is almost completely preempted by hunger.
All capacities are put into the service of hunger-satisfaction, and the organization of
these capacities is almost entirely determined by the one purpose of satisfying hunger.
The receptors and effectors, the intelligence, memory, habits, all may now be defined
simply as hunger-gratifying tools. Capacities that are not useful for this purpose lie
dormant, or are pushed into the background. The urge to write poetry, the desire to
acquire an automobile, the interest in American history, the desire for a new pair of
shoes are, in the extreme case, forgotten or become of sec-[p.374]ondary importance.
For the man who is extremely and dangerously hungry, no other interests exist but
food. He dreams food, he remembers food, he thinks about food, he emotes only about
food, he perceives only food and he wants only food. The more subtle determinants
that ordinarily fuse with the physiological drives in organizing even feeding, drinking
or sexual behavior, may now be so completely overwhelmed as to allow us to speak at
this time (but only at this time) of pure hunger drive and behavior, with the one
unqualified aim of relief.
Another peculiar characteristic of the human organism when it is dominated by a
certain need is that the whole philosophy of the future tends also to change. For our
chronically and extremely hungry man, Utopia can be defined very simply as a place
where there is plenty of food. He tends to think that, if only he is guaranteed food for
the rest of his life, he will be perfectly happy and will never want anything more. Life
itself tends to be defined in terms of eating. Anything else will be defined as
unimportant. Freedom, love, community feeling, respect, philosophy, may all be
waved aside as fripperies which are useless since they fail to fill the stomach. Such a
man may fairly be said to live by bread alone.
It cannot possibly be denied that such things are true but their generality can be
denied. Emergency conditions are, almost by definition, rare in the normally
functioning peaceful society. That this truism can be forgotten is due mainly to two
reasons. First, rats have few motivations other than physiological ones, and since so
much of the research upon motivation has been made with these animals, it is easy to
carry the rat-picture over to the human being. Secondly, it is too often not realized that
culture itself is an adaptive tool, one of whose main functions is to make the
physiological emergencies come less and less often. In most of the known societies,
chronic extreme hunger of the emergency type is rare, rather than common. In any
case, this is still true in the United States. The average American citizen is
experiencing appetite rather than hunger when he says "I am [p. 375] hungry." He is
apt to experience sheer life-and-death hunger only by accident and then only a few
times through his entire life.
Obviously a good way to obscure the 'higher' motivations, and to get a lopsided view
of human capacities and human nature, is to make the organism extremely and
chronically hungry or thirsty. Anyone who attempts to make an emergency picture
into a typical one, and who will measure all of man's goals and desires by his behavior
during extreme physiological deprivation is certainly being blind to many things. It is
quite true that man lives by bread alone -- when there is no bread. But what happens
to man's desires when there is plenty of bread and when his belly is chronically filled?
At once other (and 'higher') needs emerge and these, rather than physiological
hungers, dominate the organism. And when these in turn are satisfied, again new (and
still 'higher') needs emerge and so on. This is what we mean by saying that the basic
human needs are organized into a hierarchy of relative prepotency.
One main implication of this phrasing is that gratification becomes as important a
concept as deprivation in motivation theory, for it releases the organism from the
domination of a relatively more physiological need, permitting thereby the emergence
of other more social goals. The physiological needs, along with their partial goals,
when chronically gratified cease to exist as active determinants or organizers of
behavior. They now exist only in a potential fashion in the sense that they may emerge
again to dominate the organism if they are thwarted. But a want that is satisfied is no
longer a want. The organism is dominated and its behavior organized only by
unsatisfied needs. If hunger is satisfied, it becomes unimportant in the current
dynamics of the individual.
This statement is somewhat qualified by a hypothesis to be discussed more fully later,
namely that it is precisely those individuals in whom a certain need has always been
satisfied who are best equipped to tolerate deprivation of that need in the future, and
that furthermore, those who have been de-[p. 376]prived in the past will react
differently to current satisfactions than the one who has never been deprived.
The safety needs. -- If the physiological needs are relatively well gratified, there then
emerges a new set of needs, which we may categorize roughly as the safety needs. All
that has been said of the physiological needs is equally true, although in lesser degree,
of these desires. The organism may equally well be wholly dominated by them. They
may serve as the almost exclusive organizers of behavior, recruiting all the capacities
of the organism in their service, and we may then fairly describe the whole organism
as a safety-seeking mechanism. Again we may say of the receptors, the effectors, of
the intellect and the other capacities that they are primarily safety-seeking tools.
Again, as in the hungry man, we find that the dominating goal is a strong determinant
not only of his current world-outlook and philosophy but also of his philosophy of the
future. Practically everything looks less important than safety, (even sometimes the
physiological needs which being satisfied, are now underestimated). A man, in this
state, if it is extreme enough and chronic enough, may be characterized as living
almost for safety alone.
Although in this paper we are interested primarily in the needs of the adult, we can
approach an understanding of his safety needs perhaps more efficiently by observation
of infants and children, in whom these needs are much more simple and obvious. One
reason for the clearer appearance of the threat or danger reaction in infants, is that
they do not inhibit this reaction at all, whereas adults in our society have been taught
to inhibit it at all costs. Thus even when adults do feel their safety to be threatened we
may not be able to see this on the surface. Infants will react in a total fashion and as if
they were endangered, if they are disturbed or dropped suddenly, startled by loud
noises, flashing light, or other unusual sensory stimulation, by rough handling, by
general loss of support in the mother's arms, or by inadequate support.[1][p. 377]
In infants we can also see a much more direct reaction to bodily illnesses of various
kinds. Sometimes these illnesses seem to be immediately and per sethreatening and
seem to make the child feel unsafe. For instance, vomiting, colic or other sharp pains
seem to make the child look at the whole world in a different way. At such a moment
of pain, it may be postulated that, for the child, the appearance of the whole world
suddenly changes from sunniness to darkness, so to speak, and becomes a place in
which anything at all might happen, in which previously stable things have suddenly
become unstable. Thus a child who because of some bad food is taken ill may, for a
day or two, develop fear, nightmares, and a need for protection and reassurance never
seen in him before his illness.
Another indication of the child's need for safety is his preference for some kind of
undisrupted routine or rhythm. He seems to want a predictable, orderly world. For
instance, injustice, unfairness, or inconsistency in the parents seems to make a child
feel anxious and unsafe. This attitude may be not so much because of the injustice per
se or any particular pains involved, but rather because this treatment threatens to make
the world look unreliable, or unsafe, or unpredictable. Young children seem to thrive
better under a system which has at least a skeletal outline of rigidity, In which there is
a schedule of a kind, some sort of routine, something that can be counted upon, not
only for the present but also far into the future. Perhaps one could express this more
accurately by saying that the child needs an organized world rather than an
unorganized or unstructured one.
The central role of the parents and the normal family setup are indisputable.
Quarreling, physical assault, separation, divorce or death within the family may be
particularly terrifying. Also parental outbursts of rage or threats of punishment
directed to the child, calling him names, speaking to him harshly, shaking him,
handling him roughly, or actual [p. 378] physical punishment sometimes elicit such
total panic and terror in the child that we must assume more is involved than the
physical pain alone. While it is true that in some children this terror may represent
also a fear of loss of parental love, it can also occur in completely rejected children,
who seem to cling to the hating parents more for sheer safety and protection than
because of hope of love.
Confronting the average child with new, unfamiliar, strange, unmanageable stimuli or
situations will too frequently elicit the danger or terror reaction, as for example,
getting lost or even being separated from the parents for a short time, being
confronted with new faces, new situations or new tasks, the sight of strange,
unfamiliar or uncontrollable objects, illness or death. Particularly at such times, the
child's frantic clinging to his parents is eloquent testimony to their role as protectors
(quite apart from their roles as food-givers and love-givers).
From these and similar observations, we may generalize and say that the average child
in our society generally prefers a safe, orderly, predictable, organized world, which he
can count, on, and in which unexpected, unmanageable or other dangerous things do
not happen, and in which, in any case, he has all-powerful parents who protect and
shield him from harm.
That these reactions may so easily be observed in children is in a way a proof of the
fact that children in our society, feel too unsafe (or, in a word, are badly brought up).
Children who are reared in an unthreatening, loving family do not ordinarily react as
we have described above (17). In such children the danger reactions are apt to come
mostly to objects or situations that adults too would consider dangerous.[2]
The healthy, normal, fortunate adult in our culture is largely satisfied in his safety
needs. The peaceful, smoothly [p. 379] running, 'good' society ordinarily makes its
members feel safe enough from wild animals, extremes of temperature, criminals,
assault and murder, tyranny, etc. Therefore, in a very real sense, he no longer has any
safety needs as active motivators. Just as a sated man no longer feels hungry, a safe
man no longer feels endangered. If we wish to see these needs directly and clearly we
must turn to neurotic or near-neurotic individuals, and to the economic and social
underdogs. In between these extremes, we can perceive the expressions of safety
needs only in such phenomena as, for instance, the common preference for a job with
tenure and protection, the desire for a savings account, and for insurance of various
kinds (medical, dental, unemployment, disability, old age).
Other broader aspects of the attempt to seek safety and stability in the world are seen
in the very common preference for familiar rather than unfamiliar things, or for the
known rather than the unknown. The tendency to have some religion or worldphilosophy that organizes the universe and the men in it into some sort of
satisfactorily coherent, meaningful whole is also in part motivated by safety-seeking.
Here too we may list science and philosophy in general as partially motivated by the
safety needs (we shall see later that there are also other motivations to scientific,
philosophical or religious endeavor).
Otherwise the need for safety is seen as an active and dominant mobilizer of the
organism's resources only in emergencies, e. g., war, disease, natural catastrophes,
crime waves, societal disorganization, neurosis, brain injury, chronically bad situation.
Some neurotic adults in our society are, in many ways, like the unsafe child in their
desire for safety, although in the former it takes on a somewhat special appearance.
Their reaction is often to unknown, psychological dangers in a world that is perceived
to be hostile, overwhelming and threatening. Such a person behaves as if a great
catastrophe were almost always impending, i.e., he is usually responding as if to an
emergency. His safety needs often find specific [p. 380] expression in a search for a
protector, or a stronger person on whom he may depend, or perhaps, a Fuehrer.
The neurotic individual may be described in a slightly different way with some
usefulness as a grown-up person who retains his childish attitudes toward the world.
That is to say, a neurotic adult may be said to behave 'as if' he were actually afraid of
a spanking, or of his mother's disapproval, or of being abandoned by his parents, or
having his food taken away from him. It is as if his childish attitudes of fear and threat
reaction to a dangerous world had gone underground, and untouched by the growing
up and learning processes, were now ready to be called out by any stimulus that would
make a child feel endangered and threatened.[3]
The neurosis in which the search for safety takes its dearest form is in the compulsiveobsessive neurosis. Compulsive-obsessives try frantically to order and stabilize the
world so that no unmanageable, unexpected or unfamiliar dangers will ever appear
(14); They hedge themselves about with all sorts of ceremonials, rules and formulas
so that every possible contingency may be provided for and so that no new
contingencies may appear. They are much like the brain injured cases, described by
Goldstein (6), who manage to maintain their equilibrium by avoiding everything
unfamiliar and strange and by ordering their restricted world in such a neat,
disciplined, orderly fashion that everything in the world can be counted upon. They
try to arrange the world so that anything unexpected (dangers) cannot possibly occur.
If, through no fault of their own, something unexpected does occur, they go into a
panic reaction as if this unexpected occurrence constituted a grave danger. What we
can see only as a none-too-strong preference in the healthy person, e. g., preference
for the familiar, becomes a life-and-death. necessity in abnormal cases.
The love needs. -- If both the physiological and the safety needs are fairly well
gratified, then there will emerge the love and affection and belongingness needs, and
the whole cycle [p. 381] already described will repeat itself with this new center. Now
the person will feel keenly, as never before, the absence of friends, or a sweetheart, or
a wife, or children. He will hunger for affectionate relations with people in general,
namely, for a place in his group, and he will strive with great intensity to achieve this
goal. He will want to attain such a place more than anything else in the world and may
even forget that once, when he was hungry, he sneered at love.
In our society the thwarting of these needs is the most commonly found core in cases
of maladjustment and more severe psychopathology. Love and affection, as well as
their possible expression in sexuality, are generally looked upon with ambivalence
and are customarily hedged about with many restrictions and inhibitions. Practically
all theorists of psychopathology have stressed thwarting of the love needs as basic in
the picture of maladjustment. Many clinical studies have therefore been made of this
need and we know more about it perhaps than any of the other needs except the
physiological ones (14).
One thing that must be stressed at this point is that love is not synonymous with sex.
Sex may be studied as a purely physiological need. Ordinarily sexual behavior is
multi-determined, that is to say, determined not only by sexual but also by other
needs, chief among which are the love and affection needs. Also not to be overlooked
is the fact that the love needs involve both giving and receiving love.[4]
The esteem needs. -- All people in our society (with a few pathological exceptions)
have a need or desire for a stable, firmly based, (usually) high evaluation of
themselves, for self-respect, or self-esteem, and for the esteem of others. By firmly
based self-esteem, we mean that which is soundly based upon real capacity,
achievement and respect from others. These needs may be classified into two
subsidiary sets. These are, first, the desire for strength, for achievement, for adequacy,
for confidence in the face of the world, and for independence and freedom.[5]
Secondly, we have what [p. 382] we may call the desire for reputation or prestige
(defining it as respect or esteem from other people), recognition, attention, importance
or appreciation.[6] These needs have been relatively stressed by Alfred Adler and his
followers, and have been relatively neglected by Freud and the psychoanalysts. More
and more today however there is appearing widespread appreciation of their central
importance.
Satisfaction of the self-esteem need leads to feelings of self-confidence, worth,
strength, capability and adequacy of being useful and necessary in the world. But
thwarting of these needs produces feelings of inferiority, of weakness and of
helplessness. These feelings in turn give rise to either basic discouragement or else
compensatory or neurotic trends. An appreciation of the necessity of basic selfconfidence and an understanding of how helpless people are without it, can be easily
gained from a study of severe traumatic neurosis (8).[7]
The need for self-actualization. -- Even if all these needs are satisfied, we may still
often (if not always) expect that a new discontent and restlessness will soon develop,
unless the individual is doing what he is fitted for. A musician must make music, an
artist must paint, a poet must write, if he is to be ultimately happy. What a
man can be, he must be. This need we may call self-actualization.
This term, first coined by Kurt Goldstein, is being used in this paper in a much more
specific and limited fashion. It refers to the desire for self-fulfillment, namely, to the
tendency for him to become actualized in what he is potentially. This tendency might
be phrased as the desire to become more and more what one is, to become everything
that one is capable of becoming.[p. 383]
The specific form that these needs will take will of course vary greatly from person to
person. In one individual it may take the form of the desire to be an ideal mother, in
another it may be expressed athletically, and in still another it may be expressed in
painting pictures or in inventions. It is not necessarily a creative urge although in
people who have any capacities for creation it will take this form.
The clear emergence of these needs rests upon prior satisfaction of the physiological,
safety, love and esteem needs. We shall call people who are satisfied in these needs,
basically satisfied people, and it is from these that we may expect the fullest (and
healthiest) creativeness.[8] Since, in our society, basically satisfied people are the
exception, we do not know much about self-actualization, either experimentally or
clinically. It remains a challenging problem for research.
The preconditions for the basic need satisfactions. -- There are certain conditions
which are immediate prerequisites for the basic need satisfactions. Danger to these is
reacted to almost as if it were a direct danger to the basic needs themselves. Such
conditions as freedom to speak, freedom to do what one wishes so long as no harm is
done to others, freedom to express one's self, freedom to investigate and seek for
information, freedom to defend one's self, justice, fairness, honesty, orderliness in the
group are examples of such preconditions for basic need satisfactions. Thwarting in
these freedoms will be reacted to with a threat or emergency response. These
conditions are not ends in themselves but they are almost so since they are so closely
related to the basic needs, which are apparently the only ends in themselves. These
conditions are defended because without them the basic satisfactions are quite
impossible, or at least, very severely endangered.[p. 384]
If we remember that the cognitive capacities (perceptual, intellectual, learning) are a
set of adjustive tools, which have, among other functions, that of satisfaction of our
basic needs, then it is clear that any danger to them, any deprivation or blocking of
their free use, must also be indirectly threatening to the basic needs themselves. Such
a statement is a partial solution of the general problems of curiosity, the search for
knowledge, truth and wisdom, and the ever-persistent urge to solve the cosmic
mysteries.
We must therefore introduce another hypothesis and speak of degrees of closeness to
the basic needs, for we have already pointed out that any conscious desires (partial
goals) are more or less important as they are more or less close to the basic needs. The
same statement may be made for various behavior acts. An act is psychologically
important if it contributes directly to satisfaction of basic needs. The less directly it so
contributes, or the weaker this contribution is, the less important this act must be
conceived to be from the point of view of dynamic psychology. A similar statement
may be made for the various defense or coping mechanisms. Some are very directly
related to the protection or attainment of the basic needs, others are only weakly and
distantly related. Indeed if we wished, we could speak of more basic and less basic
defense mechanisms, and then affirm that danger to the more basic defenses is more
threatening than danger to less basic defenses (always remembering that this is so
only because of their relationship to the basic needs).
The desires to know and to understand. -- So far, we have mentioned the cognitive
needs only in passing. Acquiring knowledge and systematizing the universe have been
considered as, in part, techniques for the achievement of basic safety in the world, or,
for the intelligent man, expressions of self-actualization. Also freedom of inquiry and
expression have been discussed as preconditions of satisfactions of the basic needs.
True though these formulations may be, they do not constitute definitive answers to
the question as to the motivation role of curiosity, learning, philosophizing,
experimenting, etc. They are, at best, no more than partial answers.[p. 385]
This question is especially difficult because we know so little about the facts.
Curiosity, exploration, desire for the facts, desire to know may certainly be observed
easily enough. The fact that they often are pursued even at great cost to the
individual's safety is an earnest of the partial character of our previous discussion. In
addition, the writer must admit that, though he has sufficient clinical evidence to
postulate the desire to know as a very strong drive in intelligent people, no data are
available for unintelligent people. It may then be largely a function of relatively high
intelligence. Rather tentatively, then, and largely in the hope of stimulating discussion
and research, we shall postulate a basic desire to know, to be aware of reality, to get
the facts, to satisfy curiosity, or as Wertheimer phrases it, to see rather than to be
blind.
This postulation, however, is not enough. Even after we know, we are impelled to
know more and more minutely and microscopically on the one hand, and on the other,
more and more extensively in the direction of a world philosophy, religion, etc. The
facts that we acquire, if they are isolated or atomistic, inevitably get theorized about,
and either analyzed or organized or both. This process has been phrased by some as
the search for 'meaning.' We shall then postulate a desire to understand, to
systematize, to organize, to analyze, to look for relations and meanings.
Once these desires are accepted for discussion, we see that they too form themselves
into a small hierarchy in which the desire to know is prepotent over the desire to
understand. All the characteristics of a hierarchy of prepotency that we have described
above, seem to hold for this one as well.
We must guard ourselves against the too easy tendency to separate these desires from
the basic needs we have discussed above, i.e., to make a sharp dichotomy between
'cognitive' and 'conative' needs. The desire to know and to understand are themselves
conative, i.e., have a striving character, and are as much personality needs as the 'basic
needs' we have already discussed (19).[p. 386]
III. FURTHER CHARACTERISTICS OF THE BASIC NEEDS
The degree of fixity of the hierarchy of basic needs. -- We have spoken so far as if this
hierarchy were a fixed order but actually it is not nearly as rigid as we may have
implied. It is true that most of the people with whom we have worked have seemed to
have these basic needs in about the order that has been indicated. However, there have
been a number of exceptions.
(1) There are some people in whom, for instance, self-esteem seems to be more
important than love. This most common reversal in the hierarchy is usually due to the
development of the notion that the person who is most likely to be loved is a strong or
powerful person, one who inspires respect or fear, and who is self confident or
aggressive. Therefore such people who lack love and seek it, may try hard to put on a
front of aggressive, confident behavior. But essentially they seek high self-esteem and
its behavior expressions more as a means-to-an-end than for its own sake; they seek
self-assertion for the sake of love rather than for self-esteem itself.
(2) There are other, apparently innately creative people in whom the drive to
creativeness seems to be more important than any other counter-determinant. Their
creativeness might appear not as self-actualization released by basic satisfaction, but
in spite of lack of basic satisfaction.
(3) In certain people the level of aspiration may be permanently deadened or lowered.
That is to say, the less pre-potent goals may simply be lost, and may disappear
forever, so that the person who has experienced life at a very low level, i. e., chronic
unemployment, may continue to be satisfied for the rest of his life if only he can get
enough food.
(4) The so-called 'psychopathic personality' is another example of permanent loss of
the love needs. These are people who, according to the best data available (9), have
been starved for love in the earliest months of their lives and have simply lost forever
the desire and the ability to give and to receive affection (as animals lose sucking or
pecking reflexes that are not exercised soon enough after birth).[p. 387]
(5) Another cause of reversal of the hierarchy is that when a need has been satisfied
for a long time, this need may be underevaluated. People who have never experienced
chronic hunger are apt to underestimate its effects and to look upon food as a rather
unimportant thing. If they are dominated by a higher need, this higher need will seem
to be the most important of all. It then becomes possible, and indeed does actually
happen, that they may, for the sake of this higher need, put themselves into the
position of being deprived in a more basic need. We may expect that after a long-time
deprivation of the more basic need there will be a tendency to reevaluate both needs
so that the more pre-potent need will actually become consciously prepotent for the
individual who may have given it up very lightly. Thus, a man who has given up his
job rather than lose his self-respect, and who then starves for six months or so, may be
willing to take his job back even at the price of losing his a self-respect.
(6) Another partial explanation of apparent reversals is seen in the fact that we have
been talking about the hierarchy of prepotency in terms of consciously felt wants or
desires rather than of behavior. Looking at behavior itself may give us the wrong
impression. What we have claimed is that the person will want the more basic of two
needs when deprived in both. There is no necessary implication here that he will act
upon his desires. Let us say again that there are many determinants of behavior other
than the needs and desires.
(7) Perhaps more important than all these exceptions are the ones that involve ideals,
high social standards, high values and the like. With such values people become
martyrs; they give up everything for the sake of a particular ideal, or value. These
people may be understood, at least in part, by reference to one basic concept (or
hypothesis) which may be called 'increased frustration-tolerance through early
gratification'. People who have been satisfied in their basic needs throughout their
lives, particularly in their earlier years, seem to develop exceptional power to
withstand present or future thwarting of these needs simply because they have
strong,[p. 388] healthy character structure as a result of basic satisfaction. They are
the 'strong' people who can easily weather disagreement or opposition, who can swim
against the stream of public opinion and who can stand up for the truth at great
personal cost. It is just the ones who have loved and been well loved, and who have
had many deep friendships who can hold out against hatred, rejection or persecution.
I say all this in spite of the fact that there is a certain amount of sheer habituation
which is also involved in any full discussion of frustration tolerance. For instance, it is
likely that those persons who have been accustomed to relative starvation for a long
time, are partially enabled thereby to withstand food deprivation. What sort of balance
must be made between these two tendencies, of habituation on the one hand, and of
past satisfaction breeding present frustration tolerance on the other hand, remains to
be worked out by further research. Meanwhile we may assume that they are both
operative, side by side, since they do not contradict each other, In respect to this
phenomenon of increased frustration tolerance, it seems probable that the most
important gratifications come in the first two years of life. That is to say, people who
have been made secure and strong in the earliest years, tend to remain secure and
strong thereafter in the face of whatever threatens.
Degree of relative satisfaction. -- So far, our theoretical discussion may have given
the impression that these five sets of needs are somehow in a step-wise, all-or-none
relationships to each other. We have spoken in such terms as the following: "If one
need is satisfied, then another emerges." This statement might give the false
impression that a need must be satisfied 100 per cent before the next need emerges. In
actual fact, most members of our society who are normal, are partially satisfied in all
their basic needs and partially unsatisfied in all their basic needs at the same time. A
more realistic description of the hierarchy would be in terms of decreasing
percentages of satisfaction as we go up the hierarchy of prepotency, For instance, if I
may assign arbitrary figures for the sake of illustration, it is as if the average citizen
[p. 389] is satisfied perhaps 85 per cent in his physiological needs, 70 per cent in his
safety needs, 50 per cent in his love needs, 40 per cent in his self-esteem needs, and
10 per cent in his self-actualization needs.
As for the concept of emergence of a new need after satisfaction of the prepotent
need, this emergence is not a sudden, saltatory phenomenon but rather a gradual
emergence by slow degrees from nothingness. For instance, if prepotent need A is
satisfied only 10 per cent: then need B may not be visible at all. However, as this need
A becomes satisfied 25 per cent, need B may emerge 5 per cent, as need A becomes
satisfied 75 per cent need B may emerge go per cent, and so on.
Unconscious character of needs. -- These needs are neither necessarily conscious nor
unconscious. On the whole, however, in the average person, they are more often
unconscious rather than conscious. It is not necessary at this point to overhaul the
tremendous mass of evidence which indicates the crucial importance of unconscious
motivation. It would by now be expected, on a priori grounds alone, that unconscious
motivations would on the whole be rather more important than the conscious
motivations. What we have called the basic needs are very often largely unconscious
although they may, with suitable techniques, and with sophisticated people become
conscious.
Cultural specificity and generality of needs. -- This classification of basic needs
makes some attempt to take account of the relative unity behind the superficial
differences in specific desires from one culture to another. Certainly in any particular
culture an individual's conscious motivational content will usually be extremely
different from the conscious motivational content of an individual in another society.
However, it is the common experience of anthropologists that people, even in
different societies, are much more alike than we would think from our first contact
with them, and that as we know them better we seem to find more and more of this
commonness, We then recognize the most startling differences to be superficial rather
than basic, e. g., differences in style of hair-dress, clothes, tastes in food, etc. Our
classification of basic [p. 390] needs is in part an attempt to account for this unity
behind the apparent diversity from culture to culture. No claim is made that it is
ultimate or universal for all cultures. The claim is made only that it is
relativelymore ultimate, more universal, more basic, than the superficial conscious
desires from culture to culture, and makes a somewhat closer approach to common-
human characteristics, Basic needs are more common-human than superficial desires
or behaviors.
Multiple motivations of behavior. -- These needs must be understood not to
be exclusive or single determiners of certain kinds of behavior. An example may be
found in any behavior that seems to be physiologically motivated, such as eating, or
sexual play or the like. The clinical psychologists have long since found that any
behavior may be a channel through which flow various determinants. Or to say it in
another way, most behavior is multi-motivated. Within the sphere of motivational
determinants any behavior tends to be determined by several or all of the basic needs
simultaneously rather than by only one of them. The latter would be more an
exception than the former. Eating may be partially for the sake of filling the stomach,
and partially for the sake of comfort and amelioration of other needs. One may make
love not only for pure sexual release, but also to convince one's self of one's
masculinity, or to make a conquest, to feel powerful, or to win more basic affection.
As an illustration, I may point out that it would be possible (theoretically if not
practically) to analyze a single act of an individual and see in it the expression of his
physiological needs, his safety needs, his love needs, his esteem needs and selfactualization. This contrasts sharply with the more naive brand of trait psychology in
which one trait or one motive accounts for a certain kind of act, i. e., an aggressive act
is traced solely to a trait of aggressiveness.
Multiple determinants of behavior. -- Not all behavior is determined by the basic
needs. We might even say that not all behavior is motivated. There are many
determinants of behavior other than motives.[9] For instance, one other im-[p.
391]portant class of determinants is the so-called 'field' determinants. Theoretically, at
least, behavior may be determined completely by the field, or even by specific
isolated external stimuli, as in association of ideas, or certain conditioned reflexes. If
in response to the stimulus word 'table' I immediately perceive a memory image of a
table, this response certainly has nothing to do with my basic needs.
Secondly, we may call attention again to the concept of 'degree of closeness to the
basic needs' or 'degree of motivation.' Some behavior is highly motivated, other
behavior is only weakly motivated. Some is not motivated at all (but all behavior is
determined).
Another important point [10] is that there is a basic difference between expressive
behavior and coping behavior (functional striving, purposive goal seeking). An
expressive behavior does not try to do anything; it is simply a reflection of the
personality. A stupid man behaves stupidly, not because he wants to, or tries to, or is
motivated to, but simply because he is what he is. The same is true when I speak in a
bass voice rather than tenor or soprano. The random movements of a healthy child, the
smile on the face of a happy man even when he is alone, the springiness of the healthy
man's walk, and the erectness of his carriage are other examples of expressive, nonfunctional behavior. Also the style in which a man carries out almost all his behavior,
motivated as well as unmotivated, is often expressive.
We may then ask, is all behavior expressive or reflective of the character structure?
The answer is 'No.' Rote, habitual, automatized, or conventional behavior may or may
not be expressive. The same is true for most 'stimulus-bound' behaviors. It is finally
necessary to stress that expressiveness of behavior, and goal-directedness of behavior
are not mutually exclusive categories. Average behavior is usually both.
Goals as centering principle in motivation theory. -- It will be observed that the basic
principle in our classification has [p. 392] been neither the instigation nor the
motivated behavior but rather the functions, effects, purposes, or goals of the
behavior. It has been proven sufficiently by various people that this is the most
suitable point for centering in any motivation theory.[11]
Animal- and human-centering. -- This theory starts with the human being rather than
any lower and presumably 'simpler' animal. Too many of the findings that have been
made in animals have been proven to be true for animals but not for the human being.
There is no reason whatsoever why we should start with animals in order to study
human motivation. The logic or rather illogic behind this general fallacy of 'pseudosimplicity' has been exposed often enough by philosophers and logicians as well as by
scientists in each of the various fields. It is no more necessary to study animals before
one can study man than it is to study mathematics before one can study geology or
psychology or biology.
We may also reject the old, naive, behaviorism which assumed that it was somehow
necessary, or at least more 'scientific' to judge human beings by animal standards. One
consequence of this belief was that the whole notion of purpose and goal was
excluded from motivational psychology simply because one could not ask a white rat
about his purposes. Tolman (18) has long since proven in animal studies themselves
that this exclusion was not necessary.
Motivation and the theory of psychopathogenesis. -- The conscious motivational
content of everyday life has, according to the foregoing, been conceived to be
relatively important or unimportant accordingly as it is more or less closely related to
the basic goals. A desire for an ice cream cone might actually be an indirect
expression of a desire for love. If it is, then this desire for the ice cream cone becomes
extremely important motivation. If however the ice cream is simply something to cool
the mouth with, or a casual appetitive reaction, then the desire is relatively
unimportant. Everyday conscious desires are to be regarded as symptoms, as [p.
393] surface indicators of more basic needs. If we were to take these superficial
desires at their face value me would find ourselves in a state of complete confusion
which could never be resolved, since we would be dealing seriously with symptoms
rather than with what lay behind the symptoms.
Thwarting of unimportant desires produces no psychopathological results; thwarting
of a basically important need does produce such results. Any theory of
psychopathogenesis must then be based on a sound theory of motivation. A conflict or
a frustration is not necessarily pathogenic. It becomes so only when it threatens or
thwarts the basic needs, or partial needs that are closely related to the basic needs
(10).
The role of gratified needs. -- It has been pointed out above several times that our
needs usually emerge only when more prepotent needs have been gratified. Thus
gratification has an important role in motivation theory. Apart from this, however,
needs cease to play an active determining or organizing role as soon as they are
gratified.
What this means is that, e. g., a basically satisfied person no longer has the needs for
esteem, love, safety, etc. The only sense in which he might be said to have them is in
the almost metaphysical sense that a sated man has hunger, or a filled bottle has
emptiness. If we are interested in what actually motivates us, and not in what has,
will, or might motivate us, then a satisfied need is not a motivator. It must be
considered for all practical purposes simply not to exist, to have disappeared. This
point should be emphasized because it has been either overlooked or contradicted in
every theory of motivation I know.[12] The perfectly healthy, normal, fortunate man
has no sex needs or hunger needs, or needs for safety, or for love, or for prestige, or
self-esteem, except in stray moments of quickly passing threat. If we were to say
otherwise, we should also have to aver that every man had all the pathological
reflexes, e. g., Babinski, etc., because if his nervous system were damaged, these
would appear.
It is such considerations as these that suggest the bold [p. 394] postulation that a man
who is thwarted in any of his basic needs may fairly be envisaged simply as a sick
man. This is a fair parallel to our designation as 'sick' of the man who lacks vitamins
or minerals. Who is to say that a lack of love is less important than a lack of vitamins?
Since we know the pathogenic effects of love starvation, who is to say that we are
invoking value-questions in an unscientific or illegitimate way, any more than the
physician does who diagnoses and treats pellagra or scurvy? If I were permitted this
usage, I should then say simply that a healthy man is primarily motivated by his needs
to develop and actualize his fullest potentialities and capacities. If a man has any other
basic needs in any active, chronic sense, then he is simply an unhealthy man. He is as
surely sick as if he had suddenly developed a strong salt-hunger or calcium
hunger.[13]
If this statement seems unusual or paradoxical the reader may be assured that this is
only one among many such paradoxes that will appear as we revise our ways of
looking at man's deeper motivations. When we ask what man wants of life, we deal
with his very essence.
IV. SUMMARY
(1) There are at least five sets of goals, which we may call basic needs. These are
briefly physiological, safety, love, 'esteem, and self-actualization. In addition, we are
motivated by the desire to achieve or maintain the various conditions upon which
these basic satisfactions rest and by certain more intellectual desires.
(2) These basic goals are related to each other, being arranged in a hierarchy of
prepotency. This means that the most prepotent goal will monopolize consciousness
and will tend of itself to organize the recruitment of the various capacities of the
organism. The less prepotent needs are [p. 395] minimized, even forgotten or denied.
But when a need is fairly well satisfied, the next prepotent ('higher') need emerges, in
turn to dominate the conscious life and to serve as the center of organization of
behavior, since gratified needs are not active motivators.
Thus man is a perpetually wanting animal. Ordinarily the satisfaction of these wants is
not altogether mutually exclusive, but only tends to be. The average member of our
society is most often partially satisfied and partially unsatisfied in all of his wants.
The hierarchy principle is usually empirically observed in terms of increasing
percentages of non-satisfaction as we go up the hierarchy. Reversals of the average
order of the hierarchy are sometimes observed. Also it has been observed that an
individual may permanently lose the higher wants in the hierarchy under special
conditions. There are not only ordinarily multiple motivations for usual behavior, but
in addition many determinants other than motives.
(3) Any thwarting or possibility of thwarting of these basic human goals, or danger to
the defenses which protect them, or to the conditions upon which they rest, is
considered to be a psychological threat. With a few exceptions, all psychopathology
may be partially traced to such threats. A basically thwarted man may actually be
defined as a 'sick' man, if we wish.
(4) It is such basic threats which bring about the general emergency reactions.
(5) Certain other basic problems have not been dealt with because of limitations of
space. Among these are (a) the problem of values in any definitive motivation theory,
(b) the relation between appetites, desires, needs and what is 'good' for the organism,
(c) the etiology of the basic needs and their possible derivation in early childhood, (d)
redefinition of motivational concepts, i. e., drive, desire, wish, need, goal, (e)
implication of our theory for hedonistic theory, (f) the nature of the uncompleted act,
of success and failure, and of aspiration-level, (g) the role of association, habit and
conditioning, (h) relation to the [p. 396] theory of inter-personal relations, (i)
implications for psychotherapy, (j) implication for theory of society, (k) the theory of
selfishness, (l) the relation between needs and cultural patterns, (m) the relation
between this theory and Alport's theory of functional autonomy. These as well as
certain other less important questions must be considered as motivation theory
attempts to become definitive.
Notes
[1] As the child grows up, sheer knowledge and familiarity as well as better motor
development make these 'dangers' less and less dangerous and more and more
manageable. Throughout life it may be said that one of the main conative functions of
education is this neutralizing of apparent dangers through knowledge, e. g., I am not
afraid of thunder because I know something about it.
[2] A 'test battery' for safety might be confronting the child with a small exploding
firecracker, or with a bewhiskered face; having the mother leave the room, putting
him upon a high ladder, a hypodermic injection, having a mouse crawl up to him, etc.
Of course I cannot seriously recommend the deliberate use of such 'tests' for they
might very well harm the child being tested. But these and similar situations come up
by the score in the child's ordinary day-to-day living and may be observed. There is
no reason why those stimuli should not be used with, far example, young
chimpanzees.
[3] Not all neurotic individuals feel unsafe. Neurosis may have at its core a thwarting
of the affection and esteem needs in a person who is generally safe.
[4] For further details see (12) and (16, Chap. 5).
[5] Whether or not this particular desire is universal we do not know. The crucial
question, especially important today, is "Will men who are enslaved and dominated
inevitably feel dissatisfied and rebellious?" We may assume on the basis of commonly
known clinical data that a man who has known true freedom (not paid for by giving
up safety and security but rather built on the basis of adequate safety and security)
will not willingly or easily allow his freedom to be taken away from him. But we do
not know that this is true for the person born into slavery. The events of the next
decade should give us our answer. See discussion of this problem in (5).
[6] Perhaps the desire for prestige and respect from others is subsidiary to the desire
for self-esteem or confidence in oneself. Observation of children seems to indicate
that this is so, but clinical data give no clear support for such a conclusion.
[7] For more extensive discussion of normal self-esteem, as well as for reports of
various researches, see (11).
[8] Clearly creative behavior, like painting, is like any other behavior in having
multiple, determinants. It may be seen in 'innately creative' people whether they are
satisfied or not, happy or unhappy, hungry or sated. Also it is clear that creative
activity may be compensatory, ameliorative or purely economic. It is my impression
(as yet unconfirmed) that it is possible to distinguish the artistic and intellectual
products of basically satisfied people from those of basically unsatisfied people by
inspection alone. In any case, here too we must distinguish, in a dynamic fashion, the
overt behavior itself from its various motivations or purposes.
[9] I am aware that many psychologists md psychoanalysts use the term 'motivated'
and 'determined' synonymously, e. g., Freud. But I consider this an obfuscating usage.
Sharp distinctions are necessary for clarity of thought, and precision in
experimentation.
[10] To be discussed fully in a subsequent publication.
[11] The interested reader is referred to the very excellent discussion of this point in
Murray's Explorations in Personality (15).
[12] Note that acceptance of this theory necessitates basic revision of the Freudian
theory.
[13] If we were to use the word 'sick' in this way, we should then also have to face
squarely the relations of man to his society. One clear implication of our definition
would be that (1) since a man is to be called sick who is basically thwarted, and (2)
since such basic thwarting is made possible ultimately only by forces outside the
individual, then (3) sickness in the individual must come ultimately from sickness in
the society. The 'good' or healthy society would then be defined as one that permitted
man's highest purposes to emerge by satisfying all his prepotent basic needs.
References
1. ADLER, A. Social interest. London: Faber & Faber, 1938.
2. CANNON, W. B. Wisdom of the body. New York: Norton, 1932.
3. FREUD, A. The ego and the mechanisms of defense. London: Hogarth, 1937.
4. FREUD, S. New introductory lectures on psychoanalysis. New York: Norton, 1933.
5. FROMM, E. Escape from freedom. New York: Farrar and Rinehart, 1941.
6. GOLDSTEIN, K. The organism. New York: American Book Co., 1939.
7. HORNEY, K. The neurotic personality of our time. New York: Norton, 1937.
8. KARDINER, A. The traumatic neuroses of war. New York: Hoeber, 1941.
9. LEVY, D. M. Primary affect hunger. Amer. J. Psychiat., 1937, 94, 643-652.
10. MASLOW, A. H. Conflict, frustration, and the theory of threat. J. abnorm. (soc.)
Psychol., 1943, 38, 81-86.
11. ----------. Dominance, personality and social behavior in women. J. soc. Psychol.,
1939, 10, 3-39.
12. ----------. The dynamics of psychological security-insecurity. Character & Pers.,
1942, 10, 331-344.
13. ----------. A preface to motivation theory. Psychosomatic Med., 1943, 5, 85-92.
14. ----------. & MITTLEMANN, B. Principles of abnormal psychology. New York:
Harper & Bros., 1941.
15. MURRAY, H. A., et al. Explorations in Personality. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1938.
16. PLANT, J. Personality and the cultural pattern. New York: Commonwealth Fund,
1937.
17. SHIRLEY, M. Children's adjustments to a strange situation. J. abrnorm. (soc.)
Psychol., 1942, 37, 201-217.
18. TOLMAN, E. C. Purposive behavior in animals and men. New York: Century,
1932.
19. WERTHEIMER, M. Unpublished lectures at the New School for Social Research.
20. YOUNG, P. T. Motivation of behavior. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1936.
21. ----------. The experimental analysis of appetite. Psychol. Bull., 1941, 38, 129-164.
Purchase answer to see full
attachment