4
Copyright 2016. Routledge.
All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S. or applicable copyright law.
UTILITARIANISM
Learning Objectives
Upon completing this chapter, the reader should be able to:
••
••
••
••
••
Define utilitarianism
Discuss what is meant by the greatest happiness or good for the greatest
number
Identify and discuss similarities and differences between utilitarianism as an
approach to ethics and cost benefit analysis as used in business
Identify and discuss two major problems with the utilitarian approach
Identify and discuss the main benefit of the utilitarian approach to ethics.
Throughout the history of philosophy, thinkers have addressed the question of
what makes an act moral or immoral (for purposes of this and the following discussions, we will use the terms “moral” and “ethical” interchangeably).1 A variety
of answers have been given. In this and the following two chapters, we will
consider in some detail the three most common answers to the question. In this
chapter, we examine the approach to ethics or morality known as utilitarianism.
The Greatest Happiness or Greatest Good
Utilitarianism is the philosophical approach which says that the moral act is
the one that creates the greatest happiness or good for the greatest number
of people. Because this approach judges morality based on consequences, it is
classified as teleological. Are the greatest happiness and the greatest good the
same thing? Broadly speaking, utilitarians answer yes. In the last chapter, we saw
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS
AN: 1249059 ; Joseph Gilbert.; Ethics for Managers : Philosophical Foundations and Business Realities
Account: s4264928.main.edsebook
Utilitarianism 49
that Aristotle discussed ethics at length, principally in his Nicomachean Ethics.2 In
the first chapter of that work, he asks what might be the ultimate reason to do
something. I might practice the flute because I want to be a better flute player,
but a further logical question is why I want to become a better flute player.
Finally, there must be something which people pursue for itself (an ultimate
end) and not just because it leads to something else (an instrumental end). After
discussing various possibilities, Aristotle concludes that humans pursue as their
ultimate end “eudaimonia.”3 This Greek word has no exact English translation.
It literally means good-spiritedness. It is sometimes translated as “happiness” but
this does not capture the full flavor of the idea which Aristotle describes. The
term does not simply refer to an emotional state, but also has the sense of wellbeing of the spirit.4
Different philosophers have provided different answers to this question of the
ultimate end of human action. For Kant, it involved doing one’s duty with a
good will. For others, it involves being fully rational. Still others would describe
it as acting in accord with one’s own nature, without influence from social
conventions. The two philosophers most often associated with utilitarianism
were both Englishmen: Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Stuart Mill
(1806–1873). Bentham was particularly interested in the reform of British law.
In 1789, he published An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,5
which is perhaps the clearest statement of his views on utilitarianism. Chapter 1
opens with this statement:
Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought
to do, as well as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the
standard of right and wrong, on the other the chain of causes and effects,
are fastened to their throne.6
He defines the principle of utility as follows:
By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it
appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose
interest is in question: or, what is the same thing in other words, to promote or to oppose that happiness.7
John Stuart Mill’s work Utilitarianism was first published in 1861. In this extended
essay, he develops further and comments on Bentham’s writing on the subject.
In chapter 2, Mill says the following:
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the
Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
50 Ethical Theory
as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the
reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of
pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. To give a clear
view of the moral standard set up by the theory, much more requires to be
said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure;
and to what extent this is left an open question. But these supplementary explanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory of
morality is grounded—namely, that pleasure, and freedom from pain, are
the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are
as numerous in the utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either
for the pleasure inherent in themselves, or as means to the promotion of
pleasure and the prevention of pain.8
Results Orientation
Although it could be interesting to actually sit back and think about what
our ultimate ends might be, in most cases we make decisions based on more
immediate concerns—what philosophers would call instrumental or intermediate ends. We approve adding six new salespeople because we are persuaded
that the additional revenue they generate will not only cover their own costs,
but also provide an increment of profits to the company. However, an immediate need or opportunity for increased sales is the driving force for hiring
additional salespeople.
We choose to go to the dentist and have a root canal performed not because
we enjoy pain as an ultimate end, but because the temporary pain of the dental
procedure will result in a longer pain-free period afterward. However, current
pain and its relief may provide the stimulus to seek dental treatment.
We promote this person rather than that person not so much because it will
make either us or them happy (although it may do both) but because we expect
that they will perform well in their new job and thus produce desirable results.
However, the amount of work being delayed by having this position vacant is
an important factor in making the choice.
When we decide on the morality of an action based on the results that will
be achieved, we are engaging in utilitarianism. This is different from choosing
an action because it is simply the right thing to do. The charge is sometimes
raised that utilitarianism is wrong because it is based on the notion that the end
justifies the means. This is a saying that is often quoted, and seldom analyzed.
It is true that utilitarianism is based on ends justifying means. Because an action
will cause the greatest good for the greatest number (our end in taking the
action), the means to that end are justified or found moral. Without examining what we are doing, we often make decisions on precisely this basis. The
decision to pursue an MBA degree may mean that for the next two years the
student will have less time to spend with family and friends, less money to spend
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 51
on clothes or a car or other desirable things, and less energy left over for recreational pursuits or even for work. What justifies these results?
Utilitarianism requires that we examine second-order and even third-order
results, as well as immediate or first-order results. In the prospective student’s
mind, the knowledge and skills gained in an MBA program, or the higher level
jobs open only to individuals with this degree, or the increase in career compensation that the degree will bring, or all of these factors justify the time spent in
studying and the pleasures foregone during the MBA program. In other words,
the end justifies the means. Suppose we consider this same investment from a
different perspective. If I ask whether it is ethical for a man to choose to spend
a good part of every weekend for an extended period sitting alone reading or
typing on his computer, while depriving his wife and child of his company, you
might answer that it is certainly not ethical. At least not if he is reading about the
history of the National Football League and its teams and players, and typing his
entries in a fantasy football league. In both cases the man spends his weekends
reading and typing, but in one (pursuit of an MBA) both the man and his wife
may agree that the end (obtaining an MBA and the career opportunities that it
will bring) does justify the means. In the other case, where the end is improved
performance in his fantasy football league, perhaps no one except his fellow
players will agree that the end justifies the means.
To many people, the statement “the end justifies the means” is the same as
“a good end justifies any means.” Increased profit for my business is a good
end, but it does not justify my employing eight-year-old children for twelve
hours a day and paying them a dollar an hour. It also does not justify ignoring
safety concerns and selling a product or service with a high likelihood of harming or killing my customers. However, if my employees are seriously overpaid
and my company is about to go bankrupt due to uncompetitive pricing caused
by labor costs, reducing either wages or staff or both may well be justified in
order to keep the company operating and prevent all employees from losing
their jobs. Truth might be better served by re-phrasing the principle to say
“ends often justify means.”
Most actions of managers cause more than one result. Quite often, significant
managerial actions cause happiness for some affected individuals, and unhappiness for others. This would be true if no one had ever identified a certain
approach to ethics as utilitarianism. It does not matter in terms of the results
whether the manager intended or was aware of them or not. When ocean surf
is breaking near the shore, it is sometimes possible to stand waist-deep in water
and have approaching waves break over one’s head. If the swimmer faces the
waves, she can choose to dive into the next wave, or move quickly back toward
shore, or swim out beyond where the waves are breaking. If the swimmer stands
facing the shore and refuses to acknowledge the waves, the next one that breaks
over her head will knock her off her feet, tumble her around a bit, and provide
a less-than-pleasant experience.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
52 Ethical Theory
A manager can look forward, consider the consequences of a proposed action,
and perhaps take one of several actions to change those consequences, up to and
including not taking the proposed action. Or, the manager can refuse to face the
consequences.9 However, refusal to face them does not usually change consequences. More often it results in being knocked off one’s feet, tumbled around
a bit, and enduring a less-than-pleasant experience. Utilitarianism maintains that
the moral thing to do is to face the consequences, and to act in ways that will
maximize the happiness or the good that will result from an action. The recent
Great Recession might have been avoided or at least mitigated if managers at
financial firms had faced the likely consequences of their actions and changed
their behavior accordingly.10
The statement was made in the introductory chapter that this book has two
purposes: to make the reader aware of the ethical consequences of managerial
actions, and to provide tools for thinking through difficult ethical questions.
Utilitarianism as a perspective on ethics performs both of these functions. If we
consider whether an action will provide the greatest good or happiness for the
greatest number of people, we automatically must think about what people will
be affected, for good or for ill, by our action.
Consider the action of laying off employees. Some employees who now
work for the company will be told they no longer have jobs. The reason is not
that they have performed badly enough to be fired, or have committed offenses
that make it impossible for them to continue in their jobs. Rather, they are
being laid off because the company has more employees than it needs, and they
have been chosen for termination. Obviously the laid off employees are affected
by this decision; more than likely, so are their families. What of their fellow
employees? Someone will have to do the work formerly done by those laid
off, and the prime candidates are their fellow employees. It is logical that other
employees who were formerly comfortable in their positions will now fear for
their jobs. Morale among these employees is likely to go down. If work is not
done as well following the layoffs, customers may be affected. If the layoffs and
resultant decrease have their desired effect, profits may rise, the stock price may
go up, and stockholders may benefit.
The results described above will occur whether or not the manager deciding on
layoffs foresees them. Some people will benefit, some will be burdened. Whether
the net result is the greatest good for the greatest number or not, a number of
individuals and groups will be affected by the decision that the manager makes.
Utilitarianism requires that the manager think about these results, and calculate
their net impact, before deciding. Obviously no one can mathematically calculate
the total impact on all parties, but the manager who fails to consider and estimate
the various impacts of her action is not being moral, according to utilitarianism.
Not everyone does take such consequences into account. Financial analysts generally applaud layoffs. When a company announces that it is laying off
employees, and taking a one-time charge to cover the costs of these layoffs,
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 53
it is often the case that the company’s stock rises immediately following the
announcement. The logic that seems to lead to this result involves the conclusion that layoffs mean fewer workers, less labor cost, and hence more profits.
The impact on laid off workers and on remaining employees, and the possible consequences of being understaffed and having employees whose morale
is reduced by layoffs does not seem to be factored into the analysis that leads to
increasing stock prices as a result of layoffs.11
Cost-Benefit Analysis
Cost-benefit analysis is a utilitarian approach to evaluating proposed expenditures in business or in government. The basic concept behind cost-benefit
analysis is that spending money, time, and effort might be justified by the results
to be achieved, but it also might not. Since this sort of analysis is future-oriented,
it will necessarily be less precise than analysis of expenditures that have already
been made, and results that have already been achieved. As we will see in
Chapter 11 on ethical analysis of financial reporting, it is somewhere between
very difficult and impossible to give a fully accurate financial picture of a company or a division even using skilled accountants and analysts and the best tools
available. If this is true of events already past, the degree of accuracy obtainable
about the future is obviously even less.
Cost-benefit analysis conceptually underlies the whole process of budgeting. It does not make good business sense to plan to spend money, under either
expense or capital budgets, that will not yield a benefit at least equal to the
expenditure. The budget process is often conducted with a good deal of politics
involved, and as the saying goes, the devil is in the details. However, when
money could be spent in one of several ways, but not all of them, then aiming
to get the biggest bang for the buck is not really different from aiming to create
the greatest good for the greatest number, at least in principle.
While cost-benefit analysis is utilitarian in spirit, it is more narrow in scope.
Whether in business or in government, the most common benefit weighed
against costs is financial in nature. If a project or an addition to staff will either
generate enough revenues or reduce enough future financial cost, then it is
approved. The principal metric used in cost-benefit analysis is efficiency—will
the expenditure in question generate the most output with the least input.
While it might legitimately do so, cost-benefit analysis does not always take
into account impacts beyond expenses and revenues. To give one example frequently raised in business ethics textbooks, a cost-benefit analysis of a plant
closing in a small town might not address the impact on the town’s unemployment rate or tax base, while a utilitarian analysis would also factor in these issues
Cost-benefit analysis, by its nature, stresses quantifiable factors. However,
projects or expenditures are sometimes approved on the basis of necessity rather
than amount of dollar benefits. One relatively small hospital group with which
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
54 Ethical Theory
I am familiar recently decided to spend tens of millions of dollars integrating its
more than twenty software systems so relevant information would be available
to everyone involved with a patient from pre-admission medical work-ups to
post-discharge follow-ups. The executives of the hospital group felt that they
simply could not continue to provide adequate service without such systems
integration. The project was approved on the basis of necessity rather than of
quantified savings or additional revenue and profits. It appears that, in deciding
to spend this amount of money on systems integration, they were aiming in a
broad sense to achieve the greatest good for the greatest number.
Utilitarian analysis certainly takes costs into account. Spending money, time, or
other resources that could be spent in other ways does not, by itself, create happiness or good for anyone except the recipients. The spending is justified only if the
money, time, or other resources spent create more good or happiness than they
amount to in cost. By its focus on impacts, and its method of identifying and justifying them, utilitarianism provides a way for managers both to be aware of the impacts
of their actions and to think through the moral issues involved in a course of action.
It is good to remember that acts that are morally right can also be right in
other senses. For instance, if we consider that the goal of for-profit companies
is to make a profit (by selling airplane rides or audit services or blue jeans), then
acts that lead to or increase profits are strategically right for these companies and
their managers. If the acts are also moral (in the present case, if they lead to the
greatest good for the greatest number), then strategy and morality coincide. If
the acts are immoral (for instance, lying in financial reports), they may lead to
greater profit and hence appear strategically correct, but they are not morally
right. We will see in Chapter 11 on financial reporting that lying on financial
reports does not create the greatest good for the greatest number.
Two Important Criticisms
Two major criticisms have been made of utilitarianism as a way of viewing morality.
The first is that it is simply impractical. For most decisions that a manager makes,
there is not time to do any sort of serious analysis of the possible impacts. Some
managerial decisions have very little impact beyond the immediate and obvious.
Others are simply decisions to continue a decision process. Major decisions are
often preceded by numerous partial decisions, small steps, decisions to investigate
further, and so on. In fact, by the time a major decision is made, these smaller partial
decisions may have shaped the process in such a way that there is only one viable
option left, and what appears to be the final decision is actually anticlimactic.12
Difficulty of Implementation
If a major decision point is clearly present, the direct and indirect impacts are
likely to be such that it is difficult or impossible to quantify them even to a
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 55
reasonable degree of approximation. The time to conduct such an analysis may
not be available. Decision processes, particularly in large organizations, often
have timetables that are not determined by key participants or final decisionmakers. An issue not clearly dealt with by most utilitarians is whether to simply
count those affected positively and negatively or to also assign weights to the
degree of happiness or unhappiness that various individuals will experience as a
result of the decision. Obviously this is an important point in determining the
morality of an action by means of a utilitarian analysis. If no weight is given to
degrees of happiness or unhappiness, the analysis clearly ignores an important
element of the decision and its consequences. An individual who will suffer a
momentary bit of unease counts as much as one who will experience deep and
lasting anguish. Yet, if weights are to be assigned to varying degrees of happiness
and unhappiness, an almost overwhelming complexity is added to an already
difficult calculation.
Jeremy Bentham, the earlier of the two major utilitarian philosophers,
proposed a detailed method for calculating the greatest good for the greatest
number. He did assign degrees of importance to various forms of happiness, and
to the likelihood that an act would produce these forms. His so-called felicific
calculus, or method for determining degrees of happiness, is quite complex. As
he presents this calculus in An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,
he identifies fourteen kinds of simple pleasures, seven kinds of simple pains,
and seven circumstances affecting the value of a pain or pleasure considered by
itself.13 Bentham did indicate in the same work that it is not necessary to perform
a full calculation before each action. He says that, once a person becomes used
to the method of calculation, he will do it almost automatically, and without
long formal process, except perhaps for the occasional major decision with clear
widespread impacts.
Writing some fifty years later, John Stuart Mill, the second major utilitarian
philosopher, had the advantage of hindsight. Bentham’s work had been taken
seriously, and among the most serious criticisms leveled against it was the lack of
practicality. Mill suggests another way of determining which of two pleasures or
pains is greater. His approach is to ask those who have experienced both of the
pleasures or pains under consideration, and to accept their opinion on the ranking of the pleasures or pains in question.14 This approach is experience-based,
and does not depend on theorizing. It is also open to the charge of impracticality, since few decisions are worth the effort or can be postponed until the
opinions of several experienced persons can be gathered.
All of this may make it seem that utilitarianism is a hopelessly impractical
approach to ethics. Yet, in spite of the difficulties of doing a complete analysis, the emphasis of utilitarianism on the consequences of acts is an important
element in thinking about managerial morality. If those who packaged and
repackaged subprime mortgages had considered who would benefit and who
would suffer as a result of their actions, it would have been clear quite quickly
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
56 Ethical Theory
that many investors, lenders, business partners, and others would be hurt with
very few people deriving benefits. It would also have been clear that, by inserting bits and pieces of individual mortgages into complicated derivatives, then
selling portions of these derivatives to different investors, dealing with delinquent mortgages would become almost impossible. This is what happened, and
it caused large amounts of additional harm to individuals and institutions.15 Even
a very rough utilitarian analysis is sometimes sufficient to make clear which
course of action is ethical and which is not.16
Some Conclusions Seem Unethical
Besides the difficulty of accurately calculating the sums of happiness and unhappiness that an act might produce, the second major objection to utilitarianism
in practice is that it sometimes declares acts to be moral that would not be
approved as moral by the other two approaches to ethical reasoning, or by most
people’s basic sense of right and wrong. For instance, if I start a business, hire
nine other people, and the ten of us are doing quite well, what sort of response
can I morally make if one of my employees leaves and starts a competing business? Can I hire someone to kill my former employee? Burn down their place
of business? Tell lies about them and their product to keep my customers from
switching to them? Set my prices below theirs, even if I temporarily lose money,
in order to drive them out of business and then raise my prices?
We will see in the next two chapters that neither rights and duties nor fairness
and justice condones killing business opponents, or burning down their place of
business. These actions would also violate almost everyone’s basic sense of right
and wrong.17 Yet, if my employees and I would all benefit from the elimination
of competition from my former employee, and only the former employee (and
perhaps his family) would suffer, at least a surface reading of utilitarianism indicates that the greater good for the greater number would come about as a result
of murder or arson. There are ways to modify utilitarianism to deal with this
kind of problem. The most obvious is to assign weights to the good and harm
caused by an action, as well as simply counting those affected. We saw above
that this was proposed by Bentham, and has been criticized as creating a system
which is practically impossible to use. However, we also suggested above that
even a very crude calculation using rankings of the good and harm created might
suffice to provide a clear answer.
Another way to deal with this problem is to switch from act utilitarianism,
which judges the morality of individual acts, to rule utilitarianism, which judges
the morality of following a rule by whether the rule results in the greatest good
for the greatest number.18 One of the issues that we will see again and again in
the applied chapters of this book is that individual actions create patterns. For
instance, a manager who fills ten openings in a row within his department by
internal promotion has in fact created a pattern of excluding outside candidates,
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 57
perhaps not from consideration but indeed from being hired. Which of the ten
individual hiring/promotion decisions created this pattern? No one of them,
but all of them. A manager who overhears one racist or sexist remark from one
of her employees to another and takes no action has not created or allowed a
pattern of discrimination. However, if she overhears ten such remarks within a
month and takes no action, there is a pattern of at least tolerating discrimination.
Was it the second remark overheard without reaction that created the pattern?
The fifth? No one by itself created a pattern, but all of them, taken together, did.
Utilitarianism, at least indirectly, takes this issue of individual actions and
patterns into account when analyzing managerial decisions. Philosophers elaborating on the utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill have identified two ways of
viewing the subject: act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism.19 Act utilitarianism asks the basic question of the greatest good for the greatest number about
the results of an individual act. This approach has as one of its major drawbacks
the fact that it does not deal well, if at all, with the problem of patterns of
behavior because it concentrates its analysis only on a single act. Rule utilitarianism, in contrast, asks what the results would be in terms of the greatest
good for the greatest number if a given rule were followed. By doing so, this
approach is able to deal with the problem of patterns of behavior. However, it
adds a major level of abstraction by introducing a generalized rule that may or
may not cover an individual act, and may cover some acts more completely or
partially than others.
Rule utilitarianism is consistent with Bentham’s writings. His major work,
referred to above, is titled An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.
Bentham was very interested in reform of England’s legal system. His view was
that morality and law should be very closely joined together. A law should be
passed or kept on the books only if it created the greatest good for the greatest
number. John Stuart Mill wrote a famous essay On Liberty.20 He saw liberty as
the most basic good, and explained that all law is bad in that it constrains liberty.
However, because some selfish individuals would interfere with the liberty of
their fellow citizens, some laws are necessary to prevent them from doing so or
to punish them and provide retribution when they have done so. The test of a
good law is simply the utilitarian principle: does it provide the greatest good for
the greatest number? If it does, it should be passed or maintained. If it does not,
it should be amended or abolished.21
If we take this view one step further, and say that such an approach should
also be applied to rules of behavior that are not laws, we arrive at something very
much like rule utilitarianism. This approach to determining morality is almost
identical, in one respect, to that taken by Immanuel Kant, the most famous proponent of a duty-based approach to morality. As we will see in the next chapter,
Kant bases his view of morality on asking whether an individual act complies
with a rule that could be made universal. There is a major philosophical difference, though, in how we arrive at this point. Kant starts from the premise that
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
58 Ethical Theory
acts are moral if they comply with our intrinsic duties, and without regard to
their consequences. Bentham and Mill start from the premise that acts are moral
if they produce the greatest good for the greatest number of people, without
regard to their intrinsic rightness or wrongness.
It may well appear to the practical manager that we have now reached such
a point of useless abstraction that we will soon be discussing how many angels
can dance on the head of a pin. However, the way we arrive at a basic approach
to ethics matters a lot. If you as an individual feel that results are what matter
(and it is hard to be an effective manager without such a view), then you may
find talk of intrinsic duties to be somewhere between irrelevant and repulsive.
If, however, you as an individual feel that an excessive orientation toward
results brought us the Great Recession and an irrational emphasis on “making
the quarterly numbers,” then considerations of intrinsic duty may have a good
deal of appeal.
Any theoretical basis for morality is not going to affect the actions of individuals unless it is something with which they are at least somewhat comfortable.
The sort of discussion being conducted here of how we reach rules of conduct is
going to be very important in later chapters when we discuss whether and when
it is good to require drug tests of employees, or to indulge in creative accounting, or to lay off “excess” workers. We will talk then of patterns of behavior and
their results, and of the rights of employees, and of the duties of managers. Such
talk will not have much meaning unless we have paid serious attention to the
bases of moral and immoral decisions, and how to tell them apart.
An Ethic Based on Prediction
The two major criticisms of utilitarianism discussed above have been widely
proposed and discussed. There are ways to at least lessen its alleged impracticality, and by focusing on rules instead of individual acts, and on the quality as
well as the mere fact of pleasures and pains, the problem of the tyranny of the
majority (let’s kill him) can be eased. A third objection can be raised against
utilitarianism, and it is one that might be of particular concern to managers. If
the morality of an act (or a rule) is determined by its impacts in the future on
persons and groups known and unknown, the basis for deciding morality seems
rather frail.22 Both the physicist Neils Bohr and the baseball manager Yogi Berra
are reputed to have said, “predicting is always difficult, especially about the
future.” If a manager, who must make a lot of decisions and very seldom has full
information on which to base them, wants to be ethical, and tries to be ethical,
but may or may not succeed in being ethical because she lacks the ability to see
the future, have we really provided her with any help at all?
The central point of utilitarianism as an approach to ethics is the fact that
actions have consequences. Looking forward to an action being contemplated,
this approach requires that the manager who wants to be ethical in his actions
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 59
think through the impacts or consequences of that action. Since the manager
cannot see the future with certainty, there is room for two individuals each
doing the best job they can to disagree about a utilitarian analysis. An individual can also be honestly mistaken in his analysis of impacts—intending to
create the greatest good for the greatest number, and choosing one action rather
than another for precisely this reason, he might end up being wrong and doing
more harm than good. A manager, according to this view, might be immoral
or unethical by failing to do an analysis of the impacts of a projected action. He
might also be immoral by failing to do an honest or a competent analysis. But
if he does analyze the impacts of his actions to the best of his ability and subsequently proves wrong, he cannot really be held to have failed morally.
While this point is often missed in explanations of utilitarianism, it is an
important one. It might be more accurate to amend the definition given at the
beginning of this chapter to the following: according to utilitarianism, an act is
moral if its intended consequences following careful analysis create the greatest
good or happiness for the greatest number of people. The message for the manager wishing to be moral, then, is that accountability matters. You need to think
in advance about consequences, immediate and remote, of your actions and to
balance the good that they might do with the harm that they might create.
Thinking about consequences, immediate and remote, coincides nicely with
an approach to strategic management known as stakeholder theory that was
mentioned briefly in the previous chapter. First elaborated by Richard Freeman
in 1984,23 this theory is intended as a balance to the view that the sole proper
concern of managers is to maximize the wealth of the owners (stockholders) of
the corporation for which they work. The stakeholder view asserts that there
are a number of groups of people that either affect or are affected by a company,
and that it is the responsibility of managers to consider and balance the interests
of these stakeholder groups.
To take one example, as we will see in Chapter 11 on financial reporting,
there are different groups that rely in various ways on the public financial reports
of corporations. These groups include current and potential stockholders, creditors, regulators, taxing agencies of various governments, and others. Each group
is affected by the financial reports of the company, and makes important decisions based at least in part on these financial reports. Most of these groups can
and sometimes do have a major impact on the success or failure of the company.
Therefore, managers who do not take these various stakeholder groups into
account when making decisions (in this case, when preparing financial reports)
are ignoring a part of reality that should not be ignored. Since it is usually not
possible to please all of these groups simultaneously (taxing agencies want more
tax revenue, employees want higher wages, stockholders want more profits),
deciding on the greatest good for the greatest number is one way to approach
the demands placed on managers who consider the stakeholder view. In this
sense, the stakeholder view is at least compatible with utilitarianism.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
60 Ethical Theory
A manager who makes no decisions does not earn her salary. Decisionmaking is basic to the work of the manager. It is not her only task, but it is
absolutely, fundamentally one of her tasks. Whether she manages accountants,
sales clerks, nuclear physicists or bus drivers, she must make decisions to do her
job as manager. So, a book on managerial ethics, such as this one, cannot escape
the serious consideration of managerial decision-making. Is the premise that you
may or may not have been ethical in your decision-making—wait and see—the
best that utilitarianism can offer?
Once upon a time, there was a program for evaluating and compensating
managers known as Management by Objectives. The program has largely gone
away, but the idea and the practice are still very much alive.24 The basic idea
was as follows. At the beginning of some period (usually a calendar year), the
manager and her boss would sit down together and discuss what the manager
could contribute in the following period to the progress of the organization. If
she managed the mailroom, the objectives might involve timeliness of mail handling, cost of operation of the mailroom, success in supporting the new business
brought in by the sales goal of 15 percent more customers, and personal growth
in the manager’s business knowledge. These might all be agreed to be worthy
goals and objectives that would help the boss help the company with its overall
objectives. The goals would then be specified and, to the extent possible, quantified. They would be put in writing.
A year later, the manager and her boss would sit down for a performance
evaluation or appraisal. The agreed-upon goals would be brought out and discussed. If the manager met or exceeded her goals, she would be praised, and
rated highly, and at least in a good year, properly compensated for her fine
performance. The interesting question is what happened if she did not meet or
exceed one or more of her goals. She would undoubtedly plead unforeseeable
circumstances, or inadequate resources, or failure to cooperate by other managers whose input was essential to her goals, or bad karma, or almost anything
except personal failure. If the discussion remained rational (not always the case),
the manager might successfully plead that, in light of unpredicted and unpredictable circumstances, her performance had been heroic. She might argue that, but
for her outstanding managerial efforts, the results would have been even worse,
as indeed they were for the company’s three main competitors.
Her boss might argue that, but for her lack of foresight in making predictions,
the manager would have met and indeed, exceeded her goals. However, this is a
tricky argument for the boss to make, especially if he signed off on the objectives
a year ago. The boss might argue that the objectives were sound, but the manager’s decisions through the year as to how to meet the objectives were a wee
bit shaky (or perhaps, spectacularly dumb). If the boss was not asked to approve
these interim decisions, he can argue more firmly as to their inadequacy.
There are several things to note here. The stakes are relatively high. The
manager may receive a lower raise, or no raise, or a negative performance
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 61
appraisal that not only offends her personally but also remains permanently in
her personnel file. The boss may have a difficult interview with his boss, because
the manager’s failure to achieve objectives has now become the boss’s failure to
achieve objectives. The basis for judgment is predictions. As it turns out, the
future was indeed difficult to predict. The present argument turns on that very
point. Things change over the course of a year—any year. If the manager and
the boss are being even semi-rational, they will both acknowledge this. The key
issue is whether the changes could or should have been foreseen, and what reaction was appropriate once they came into evidence.
In this scenario, performance is being evaluated not on the basis of morality,
but on the basis of practical achievement or non-achievement of stated objectives. The criterion of evaluation is not morality but efficiency, or economic
soundness, or some other roughly quantifiable basis. However, we can note
several similarities to out earlier problem with basing moral decisions on future
events. The manager’s job includes prediction of the future. When she and her
boss sit down to set the next year’s objectives, it is assumed that whatever happens next year, it will not be an exact repeat of this year. History does not repeat
itself in this way. It is also assumed that everything will not be different. Some of
the same products or services will be sold to some of the same customers using
some of the same resources to deliver the goods. The basis for next year’s goalsetting is rational analysis, not poetry or science fiction or astrology.
Managers take it for granted that it is both possible and useful to think about
the future using the past as a guideline. Similar thinking can be used for the
predictions necessary to make moral judgments using utilitarian principles. It is
reasonable to assume that employees laid off from their jobs will find this disrupting to their lives. Unless there are special circumstances, it is reasonable to
assume that they will see the layoff as having a negative impact on them, or in
our present terms, in creating unhappiness rather than happiness. It is possible
that one of these employees who has been deeply dissatisfied with his job may
find the layoff to be the stimulus to find a new and more suitable job, thus seeing the end result as producing more good than harm for him. In spite of this
possibility, it is reasonable for a manager trying to sort out the morality of layoffs
to predict that for the employees involved, the action will create more unhappiness than happiness.
Management by Objectives is not as widely popular a program as it once was,
but the principles embodied in it continue to be used in management planning.
Budgets, whether expense, capital, or sales are standard tools. In a real sense,
a budget is a means of setting and monitoring objectives and progress toward
them. Since managers are routinely expected to predict the future economic
impacts of their decisions, it seems reasonable to ask that they also predict the
future moral impacts. Thus the objection to utilitarianism that it makes morality
depend on results in an uncertain future can be dealt with. Any system of ethics,
including the ones we will examine in the next two chapters, is useful only if it
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
62 Ethical Theory
helps to analyze the future impacts of proposed actions. A system that could only
analyze the results already achieved of actions already taken might provide an
interesting historical perspective, but could not really guide the decision-making
that is an essential part of a manager’s job.
Usefulness of Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism is one of three perspectives on morality that we consider at length
in this book. It is not an easy system to use, especially for a time-constrained
manager who does not have the luxury of reading great books and thinking
great thoughts. It does have a tendency, at least in some of its forms, to find
morally acceptable acts that most of us would instinctively agree are morally
repugnant. If it were the only way to assess the moral validity of our proposed
actions, it would leave us in deep trouble some of the time.
Given all of that, this approach to morality does something valuable and
provides insights that might not otherwise be seen. With its focus on the results
of our actions, it makes us examine the likely impacts of our choices, including
those we might prefer not to think about. Earlier in the chapter, the analogy was
used of a swimmer who can face the waves and deal with them, or face away
from them and be tossed by them. Utilitarianism, with all its imperfections,
requires us to face the waves. To use an example we have been citing, consider
the decision to implement layoffs. If we confine the analysis to financial results,
layoffs often look desirable. After all, fewer employees means less labor cost,
and less cost usually means more profit. Utilitarianism does not automatically
bar layoffs, but it makes us consider that among the results of our managerial
decision to reduce staff, one certain consequence is unhappiness on the part of
those laid off. As we will see in Chapter 9, this may be an acceptable price to pay
for the continued employment of the rest of our employees. Nonetheless, the
consequence is real and utilitarianism requires us to consider it as one element
in our decision-making.
It is not always moral to make people happy, or immoral to make them
unhappy. If we reduced prices by 50 percent across the board, and raised wages
by a similar amount, we could create happy customers and happy workers, at
least for a short while. Why not do so? We would almost certainly create a bankrupt company, with fewer (or no) workers, very unhappy investors and lenders,
and longer-range happiness would be pretty much limited to bankruptcy attorneys. Most managers instinctively know this, so we do not see many companies
simultaneously slashing prices and inflating wages.
Sometimes industries, especially if they have strong labor unions, get caught
up in the situation where they take actions almost certain to produce long-term
unhappiness for many individuals. Tens of thousands of retired American auto
workers now receive health insurance and pension benefits that create enormous burdens for the companies paying them, and for their current workers,
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 63
investors, lenders, and customers. Even though they were threatened with very
costly strikes at the time these retiree benefits were granted and augmented, it
might be that the greatest good for the greatest number in the long run would
have been achieved if executives had denied or limited these benefits. It was
undoubtedly easier for managers to grant these benefits because of the practice
of pattern bargaining, by which benefits gained by the union at one company
were automatically granted by their competitors in the same industry. Similar
issues exist as local and state governments strain to fund retirement benefits for
public employees. This is another example of the importance of patterns of decisions, as well as individual decisions.
In Chapter 3, we said that ethics has to do with social interactions. We have
seen that the nature of managerial work requires such interactions, no matter
what industry the manager works in, or at what level the manager is situated.
One of the more interesting issues in organizational theory is the question of
what it means to say that an organization decided something or did something.
Ultimately, organization decisions are human decisions. Managers, alone or in
groups, decide how an organization will acquire and use resources, what it will
sell, to whom it will sell it, and how all of this business will be conducted. These
decisions have consequences. Utilitarianism helps managers to think through the
ethical consequences of their decisions. This is no small contribution.
Discussion Questions
••
••
••
••
••
Give examples of current laws that are based on utilitarian thinking. These
can be civil or criminal laws. Give examples of laws that are clearly not
compatible with utilitarian thinking.
Teachers often tell classes that it is unethical to cheat on exams, even though
it is not illegal. Discuss whether and how this position is consistent with the
utilitarian approach to ethics.
In the United States, workers (even those who are decades away from old
age) must pay Medicare tax on their wages. This tax provides payment for
health care for those who are sixty-five or older, with some exceptions. Is
this consistent with utilitarian thinking? Why or why not?
Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, the two philosophers most identified
with utilitarianism, both maintained that the only reason to pass or retain
any law was that it would create the greatest good for the greatest number.
Do you agree with this? Why or why not?
Some coaches of youth sports (Little League baseball, youth soccer) for
younger children make it a rule that every player, whatever their skill level,
will play part of every game. Other coaches play their best players for the
whole game, increasing the team’s chance of winning and following the
practice of most competitive sports. Which of these practices is most in
accord with the utilitarian approach and why?
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
64 Ethical Theory
••
••
As quoted in a previous chapter, Milton Friedman argued that the duty of
managers is to make money for a company’s owners, and not to spend the
company’s money on other causes. He would oppose using company profits to support community schools or hospitals. Could or should a utilitarian
endorse this position? Why or why not?
Some large companies in the United States, such as Walmart and
McDonald’s, have made an effort to hire older workers (past normal retirement age) for some positions. Would a utilitarian approve or disapprove of
this effort, and why?
Notes
1 Both Plato and Aristotle, two of the earliest and most influential philosophers in
Western history, wrote extensively about ethics. Many of Plato’s dialogues have ethics either as their main theme or as a major subject. The Republic, a long dialogue in
which Plato suggests that we can best understand justice for individuals by examining
it “writ large” in the State, is still widely read and cited in college courses and in writings on ethics. Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics, his major work on this topic, is also widely
read and cited.
2 Aristotle. (1990/1926). The Nicomachean ethics, trans. H. Rackham. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press. It should be noted that Aristotle’s basic approach to ethics
is not utilitarian. He espoused an approach since known as virtue ethics.
3 “Happiness, therefore, being found to be something final and self-sufficient, is the End
at which all actions aim.” Ibid., p. 31.
4 In his translation of the Nicomachean ethics, Rackham notes in a footnote that “This
translation [happiness] of eudaimonia can hardly be avoided, but it would perhaps be
more accurately rendered by ‘Well-being’ or ‘Prosperity’; and it will be found that the
writer does not interpret it as a state of feeling but as a kind of activity.” Ibid., p. 10
footnote a.
5 Bentham, J. (1996/1789). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. New
York: Oxford University Press.
6 Mill, J. S. & Bentham, J. (1987). Utilitarianism and other essays. New York: Penguin
Books, p. 65.
7 Ibid., p. 65
8 Ibid., p. 278. While this statement refers to “the party in question,” it is clear throughout Bentham’s writings that he is concerned not just with an individual’s happiness or
good, but with that of the greatest number.
9 This may seem like a rather childish approach for a manager to take. Nonetheless,
one is struck in reading about the various companies that went bankrupt because of
managerial irresponsibility (including numerous criminal acts) in the early years of
the twenty-first century how many managers simply refused to face consequences.
Parmalat, the Italian dairy company, falsified a bank account said to contain just under
$5 billion in company assets. Managers simply made up the account. How they could
think there would be no consequences is hard to fathom, but apparently they simply
did not consider consequences. Enron managers constructed such a convoluted tangle
of special purpose entities and internal accounting transfers that it appears even the
company’s top management did not know the full extent of its debt at the time it fell.
HealthSouth’s top managers met every quarter to decide what accounts to falsify and
in what amounts in order to report the earnings expected by financial analysts. The
consequences of such repeated lies did not deter them from continuing such practices.
Many a manager in real life has refused to face the waves. Bad things often followed.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Utilitarianism 65
10 Financial Crisis Inquiry Commission. (2011). The financial crisis inquiry report. New
York: Public Affairs.
11 For a more detailed analysis of this issue, see Gilbert, J. (2000). Sorrow and guilt: An
ethical analysis of layoffs. SAM Advanced Management Journal 65:2, 4–13.
12 An excellent, book-length treatment in plain English of how such decisions actually
work in large companies is Bower, J. (1986). Managing the resource allocation process: A
study of corporate planning and investment, revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Business School Press.
13 Mill & Bentham, Utilitarianism, pp. 86–98.
14 Mill & Bentham, Utilitarianism, pp. 279–282.
15 Gilbert, J. (2011). Moral duties in business and their societal impacts: The case of the
subprime lending mess. Business and Society Review 116:1, 87–107.
16 In his book The idea of justice, Amartya Sen argues that many writers on ethics concern themselves only with describing the perfectly just society. He says that it is as
important or more important to think carefully about how to cure or improve individual situations that are unjust, making the pursuit of philosophy in this case closer
to the real world. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
17 Sen discusses the importance of recognizing ethical intuitions as well as using reason
and objectivity in his book The idea of justice, ch. 1
18 Nathanson, S. (2014). Act and rule utilitarianism. The internet encyclopedia of philosophy,
www.iep.utm.edu/ (accessed August 17, 2015).
19 See Frey, E. (2000). Act-Utilitarianism. In LaFollette, H. (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to
ethical theory. Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 165–182; and Hooker, B. (2000). RuleConsequentialism. In LaFollette (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to ethical theory, pp. 183–204.
20 Mill, J. S. (1974/1859). On liberty. London: Penguin Books.
21 Many philosophers, beginning with Plato and Aristotle, have taken the view that
political theory is simply ethics writ large. They have seen, as did Mill, the issue
of law as being very much intertwined with the issue of individual behavior and
morality. In this sense, Mill is in line with the history of philosophy on the relation
of ethical and legal issues. Mill also discusses why it is necessary to have a law prohibiting murder, even if the victim causes more harm than good to the world. Mill,
J. S. (1965). Dr. Whewell on moral philosophy. In Schneewind, J.B. (Ed.), Mill’s ethical
writings. New York: Macmillan, p. 189.
22 See Nathanson, Act and rule utilitarianism, Section 1c.
23 Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice-Hall. See also Donaldson,T. & Preston, L. (1995).The stakeholder theory
of the corporation: Concepts, evidence, implications. Academy of Management Review,
20: 65–91.
24 Management by Objectives has been considered by some to be a passing fad. For an
interesting perspective on whether this is true, on management fads in general, and on
the ways that Management by Objectives continues to be operative in current management practice, see Gibson, J. & Tesone, D. (2001). Management fads: Emergence,
evolution, and implications for managers. Academy of Management Executive, 15:4,
122–133.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:20 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
5
Copyright 2016. Routledge.
All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S. or applicable copyright law.
RIGHTS AND DUTIES
Learning Objectives
Upon completing this chapter, the reader should be able to:
••
••
••
••
••
Define the rights and duties approach to ethics
Discuss the meaning and importance of human rights
Discuss the social contract theory explaining why governments can award
rights and impose duties
Identify and discuss some of the ways that contracts can create rights and
duties that would not otherwise exist
Identify and discuss examples of position rights and duties that managers
have by their position as manager.
The second of the three major approaches to ethics that we consider in this
book is that of rights and duties. This title refers to several somewhat different
ethical views, and the works of many philosophers can be included under this
title. Broadly speaking, the rights and duties approach focuses on doing things
that are right in themselves, rather than right because of their consequences.
This approach says that the moral act is the act which recognizes the rights of
others and the duties that those rights impose on the actor.
Ethics, as we have seen, is the study of interpersonal values and the rules of
conduct that follow from them. The rights and duties approach to ethics puts
a high value on the rights of others in our interpersonal conduct. While utilitarianism is concerned with general impacts (the greatest good for the greatest
number), rights and duties are concerned more with people as individuals. This
perspective accepts the fact that we have duties, or moral obligations, to do things
or avoid doing things because we care about the rights of others. While this
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS
AN: 1249059 ; Joseph Gilbert.; Ethics for Managers : Philosophical Foundations and Business Realities
Account: s4264928.main.edsebook
Rights and Duties 67
p erspective implies that we also have rights, and other people have moral duties
to us, the main focus is on deciding whether an act is ethical based on the rights
of other individuals and the duties that those rights impose on us.
Why should we put such a high value on other people’s rights and let them
influence or determine our own rules of conduct? Sometimes it is from a basic
sense of how people ought to be treated—humans should not own each other
(as in slavery). Sometimes the answer involves reciprocity—do unto others as
you would have them do unto you, or I will observe your rights and you
will observe mine. Sometimes the reciprocity involves terms agreed to in a
contract—I will perform certain acts in exchange for certain compensation.
Sometimes it involves fear—if I fail to recognize someone’s legal right, the punishment that I will incur will be more costly to me than acting in a way that does
recognize their right.
Americans are perhaps the most rights-oriented people in history. We speak
of having a right to free speech, a right to public education, a right to our place
in line, and a right to health care. We often do not give much thought to these
rights, but simply proclaim them. A right is worthless if no one has a corresponding duty. My right to free speech imposes a duty on others not to censor
my comments or writings. My right to privacy imposes a duty on others to leave
me alone. If I have a right to health care, someone or some organization must
have a duty to provide it, or else my right is worthless. It is a commonplace of
contemporary culture in many countries that people are far more conscious of
and insistent on their rights than they are on their duties.
Definitions of Rights and Duties
While rights are often proclaimed, and duties sometimes acknowledged, there
is often a lack of clarity in the discussion of rights and duties once it proceeds
beyond proclamation and acknowledgment. Just what are rights and duties?
One common approach divides rights into claims and privileges. A worker who
starts a job with a company at an agreed-upon salary has a right to be paid that
salary as long as she is performing the job adequately and the agreement is not
changed. That right is a claim on the employer to pay the specified salary to the
worker. The same worker has a right to walk on a public sidewalk on her way
to a nearby restaurant for lunch, but it is difficult to define this right as a claim
against someone or some organization. It makes more intuitive sense to think of
this right as a privilege, but it can be seen as a claim against government to honor
her freedom to public access.
Philosophical discussion of rights frequently involves discussion of liberty.
Isaiah Berlin, in a very famous essay on “Two concepts of liberty,” defines
what he calls positive and negative freedom or liberty. He says that the positive
sense of liberty “is involved in the answer to the question ‘What or who is the
source of control or interference that can determine someone to do, or be, this
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
68 Ethical Theory
rather than that?’” He says that the negative sense of liberty “is involved in the
answer to the question ‘What is the area within which the subject—a person or
group of persons—is or should be left to do or be what he is able to do or be,
without interference by other persons?’”1 Positive liberty might be viewed as
corresponding to claim rights, and negative liberty to privilege rights. Without
liberty, the freedom to choose between alternative actions, ethics is meaningless. If all of our choices are determined, whether by genetics or circumstances
or some combination of factors, then we do not choose because we place some
values over others.
Rights can also be defined using logic to identify situations where one person
or group has a claim on another. This approach is almost mathematical in nature,
and makes extensive use of definitions that include such terms as “if and only if.”
This approach lends itself more to legal than to ethical analysis. It appears to follow
the goal of clear thinking which is characteristic of philosophy, but its main goal is
precise determination of who has rights rather than a definition of what they are.2
Duties are sometimes defined simply as the other side of rights. This approach
makes sense especially with claim rights. If I have a right to be paid for my work,
my employer has a duty to pay me. Somewhat more generally, if I have a right
to be considered as a job applicant without regard to my race, any employer to
whom I apply for a job has a duty to consider me without regard to my race.
More generally still, if I have a right to walk on a public sidewalk, government
in particular and people in general have a duty to let me walk there unimpeded.
Some philosophers such as Immanuel Kant begin from duties and reason
their way to rights. Kant emphasizes the duty to be consistent in our ethical
rules and to treat all humans with proper respect. We discuss Kant’s views in
more detail later in this chapter. Some natural rights philosophers put at least as
much emphasis on duties as on rights. This involves a difference in emphasis, but
such reasoning often ends up with the same ethical conclusion as an approach
that emphasizes rights and views duties as the logical consequence of someone
having a right.
It is generally agreed that groups as well as individuals can have both rights
and duties. As we will see below, some rights are granted by governments to
their citizens. Each individual citizen of the United States has a right to free
assembly, but an assembly by its nature involves a group. Companies, which are
legal persons, have both rights and duties as a group of employees. One of the
difficult questions in analyzing rights and duties is the extent to which groups
rather than individuals have rights and duties. We will discuss this issue further in
the second part of the book when we take up particular issues of discrimination.
Sources of Rights and Duties
There are four basic sources of rights. Some rights we have as humans, without
regard to position or citizenship or wealth or skill. Some rights we have by law.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 69
Some rights accrue to us by reason of our position. Finally, some rights have their
source in contracts. Rights from each of these sources imply duties. Depending
on the source of the rights, the corresponding duties fall upon individuals or
groups that might be in daily contact with us, or might be quite remote from
us. In order to understand how rights and duties can serve as a basis for ethical
judgment, we will now consider each of the four sources of rights.
Human Rights
Human rights is a term that is used very loosely.3 The concept has roots
extending back hundreds of years, and is built into the American legal system as a foundation.4 The Declaration of Independence says, “We hold these
truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed
by their Creator with certain unalienable rights, that among these are life,
liberty and the pursuit of happiness.”5 Almost a hundred years later, at a battlefield in Gettysburg Pennsylvania, Abraham Lincoln said, “Four score and
seven years ago, our fathers brought forth on this continent a new nation,
conceived in liberty and dedicated to the proposition that all men are created
equal.”6 One hundred years later, in a historic speech to a quarter million of
his fellow citizens gathered before the Lincoln Memorial, Martin Luther King
said, “When the architects of our republic wrote the magnificent words of
the Constitution and the Declaration of Independence, they were signing a
promissory note to which every American was to fall heir. This note was a
promise that all men would be guaranteed the inalienable rights of life, liberty,
and the pursuit of happiness.”7
Another approach to defining rights comes from the theory of natural law.
According to this view, an individual who reasons correctly about the nature of
humans and their relation to each other and to the rest of the world will identify
and recognize rights that all humans have, and the duties that correspond to
those rights. This approach refers to the natural law in the sense that all humans
have a special nature that sets them apart from other living things and from
inanimate objects.8 For instance, humans, because of their ability to reason, have
a right to think and to speak freely and should not be owned as slaves.
What are these natural or inalienable rights, and are they American or British
or Brazilian, or are they human? The most basic right that a person can have
is the right to life. In this context, we are not using the phrase as code for an
anti-abortion position, but rather we are talking of the right not to be randomly
killed. As far as I am aware, no society has ever condoned random killing—the
taking of another’s life for no reason at all. If someone said to us, “I hope Steve
feels better tomorrow—this morning he woke up grumpy and killed the first
three people he met,” we would not accept this as a fact of life like the weather.
If Steve killed even one person just because he was grumpy, we would find him
and incarcerate him.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
70 Ethical Theory
Different societies and cultures have different concepts of what makes a valid
reason to take another person’s life. Capital punishment is hotly debated in the
United States, and is abhorred in some parts of the world, but underlying the
debate is the question of whether the State can take a person’s life because of
any crime they have committed, no matter how serious.9 Through most of
history, most people have felt that it was moral for combatants in a just war to
take the lives of enemy combatants.10 There has been considerably more debate
about whether it is moral to take the lives of civilians on the other side in a war.
Self-defense is generally considered to be a valid reason to take an attacker’s life.
Because ethical systems, religions, and legal systems all deal with many of the
same values, it should not be surprising that all major religions have some form
of “Thou shalt not kill” as part of their commandments or behavioral codes.11
Similarly, all of the major legal systems proscribe murder, and define the illegal
taking of human life, along with its prescribed penalties. Donald Brown, an
anthropologist, developed a list of universal human values which occur in every
known society. Among these values are distinguishing right and wrong and
proscribing murder.12 Using induction, the method of reasoning that proceeds
from specific examples to form general rules, it seems clear that the right to life
is not based simply on societal norms or legal systems or religious belief, but is
fundamental to human value systems and has been throughout known history.13
The next human right is called by various names, and sometimes identified as several different rights. We will simply call it the right to dignity.
This encompasses the right to some freedoms, to truth-telling, and to privacy.
Various arguments can be made for why all humans have the rights included
under dignity. However, as K. Anthony Appiah has stated, “We do not need
to agree that we are all created in the image of God, or that we have natural
rights that flow from our human essence, to agree that we do not want to be
tortured by government officials, that we do not want our lives, families, and
property forfeited.”14 A number of philosophers have noted that human rights
can be grounded in several different theories, and that it is a sign of the strength
of the argument for human rights that different approaches lead to the same
conclusions.15
While it may seem strange at first glance, a very strong case can be made for
including truth-telling as part of the right to dignity.16 There are two ways to
establish such a right. One, using the deductive approach, is to consider the fact
that ongoing significant interaction between humans is impossible if there is no
distinction made between lying and truth-telling. There are certainly instances
where lying is expected—consider the rituals of early claims and demands in
labor–management negotiations—but if lying is as likely as truth-telling, discourse breaks down very quickly. We do not often think about this, but in
normal human discourse the default setting is truth-telling. Otherwise, “Are you
lying to me?” would be a meaningless question, since the answer would have an
equal chance of being the truth or another lie.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 71
The second way to establish a human right to truth-telling is to consider that
religious, legal, and moral systems all deal with this issue as an important one,
and all start from the basis that it is wrong to lie. Using inductive reasoning, we
can conclude from this large and diverse body of value systems that truth-telling
is a central value. No religious, legal, or ethical system starts from the premise
that lying is neutral or positive. Most systems provide at least some circumstances when lying might be acceptable (although some are absolute in their
prohibition), but none treats lying as a valid starting point and then asks when it
is acceptable to tell the truth.
The human right to dignity also includes protection against such things
as slavery and torture, and some right to privacy. The frequent appearance
throughout history of both slavery and torture, and various violations by many
societies of even rudimentary individual privacy make the argument here more
difficult. While it is hard for contemporary citizens of the United States to imagine a satisfactory life without such a right, our previous method of establishing
rights inductively by finding universal or near-universal examples does not work
so well here. However, as noted above, the fact that some individuals find the
basis for such rights in one theory, and others in other theories, does not weaken
the argument for such rights.
Legal systems deal in various ways with the elements of the right to dignity. Just what the right consists of is a difficult question to which no generally
agreed-upon answer has been found. Most philosophers agree that liberty is
part of this concept.17 The reason why such an issue matters is that rights that
are fundamental to all humans will provide an important starting point in dealing with issues concerning multinational business practices. It is one thing to
establish that a given society or country disapproves of bribery or full-time work
by twelve year olds. It is another to establish that a given practice violates fundamental human rights, because these rights do not depend on the laws or even
the customs of a given country or society.
There is almost certainly a human right to own property, although there is
a small body of evidence to the contrary. Thomas Hobbes was an English philosopher who influenced many of the Founding Fathers of the United States.
He maintains in his famous work Leviathan18 that without some arrangement to
keep the strong from taking whatever they want from the weak, there would
be a constant war of all against all, and life would be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Human history is full of examples of individuals and groups
who were not satisfied with “their own” food, property, wives, or slaves and
took “someone else’s” without permission or compensation. However, in those
societies where the norm has been to simply answer in kind, life has typically
degenerated to a point where Hobbes’s description seems accurate.
Again, religious, legal, and moral systems all deal with some variation of
“Thou shalt not steal.” The exception referred to above is that some examples
exist of groups that do not allow for individual ownership of any property.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
72 Ethical Theory
Economic communism maintains that society should operate on the basis of
“from each according to his ability; to each according to his needs.”19 For the
most part, countries under the political system of communism have modified
this pure economic theory to varying degrees, but they have functioned, some
for several generations, according to this basic principle. Needless to say, this
principle does not easily co-exist with private property. Some religious groups,
such as Catholic religious orders, have practiced a very pure form of economic
communism for hundreds of years. Each member of the group takes a vow of
poverty, and all property is owned by the group rather than by any individual
member. In the early decades of the kibbutz movement in Israel, common ownership of property and the means of production was a key feature of this way of
life.20 Various utopian groups have lived more or less without individual property in different countries at different times.
In spite of the exceptions cited above, the overwhelming majority of people throughout history have recognized some form of individual ownership of
property. This is true at least in the sense that something (food, clothing, a hut,
or house) is mine or yours, but is not anyone’s simply for the taking. Under
varying conditions and to varying degrees, humans have been viewed as property and have come under property laws, but this is a complex issue not directly
relevant to contemporary managers.21 Again, religious, legal, and moral systems
all deal with some variant of “Thou shalt not steal.” Such prohibitions are meaningless if no one owns anything. This, then, is evidence that in most religions
and societies through most of recorded history there has been an acceptance of
the notion that individuals own things.
Human rights, then, if carefully examined, are relatively few but very
important. Of course, it is not necessary that all humans everywhere agree that
something is a human right for it to be so. There is a tendency to widen the
range of human rights when discussing this subject. It is important to remember
that rights are practically useless without corresponding duties. Perhaps some
people who are quite free in listing a wide range of human rights would be
somewhat more cautious in this endeavor if they gave full consideration to the
range of human duties that they are simultaneously positing.
Legal Rights
The second source of rights is legal rights. These are rights granted to citizens
of a government unit or to corporations or other groups by law.22 They are
enforceable through court systems. Some legal rights embody human rights;
others do not. There is both a legal right and a human right to life which manifests itself in a duty not to randomly kill people. We showed above why this is
a human right. It is also a right in legal systems, although different legal systems
have different definitions of random killing. There is a legal right to walk on a
public sidewalk, but it scarcely qualifies as a human right. In contrast to human
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 73
rights which are the same everywhere, legal rights vary by place and time. As we
will see in Chapter 9, companies in the United States have fewer legal restrictions on terminating employees than companies in many European countries.
In Chapter 13, we discuss at length several issues that arise for multinational
companies as a result of varying laws, regulations, and customs.
Different jurisdictions within a country can and do grant different legal rights,
but the hierarchy of jurisdictions is made clear by legal systems. In the United
States, the Federal Constitution spells out the areas in which federal laws take
precedence. Generally speaking, areas not specifically reserved to the federal
government are open for law-making by states and lower governments such
as counties and cities.23 In some countries, there is a single state religion, and
religious authorities also make and interpret the laws. The United States, more
than many other countries, is very careful to recognize the separation of church
and state. Perhaps this is because from its founding the United States has been
a pluralistic society, accommodating individuals of many different beliefs and of
no belief. The first ten amendments to the U.S. Constitution, generally known
as the Bill of Rights, guarantee freedoms to American citizens that are greater
than those provided under many other governments.
We may well ask where governments get the power to grant rights and
impose duties. In a democracy, the standard answer is that governments derive
their power from the people. Some individuals are elected by the voting citizens
to represent them (the voters) in deciding what government shall do, and how it
shall do it. If these elected representatives do not in fact represent the people at
large in a satisfactory way, they can be voted out of office at the next scheduled
election. In extreme cases, they can be removed before a scheduled election by
impeachment or by recall. In a monarchy, government power resides in the
monarch. He or she may hold that position by heredity or by force, but the
literal meaning of democracy is rule by the people, while monarchy means rule
by one. In a government of religious establishment, the leader or leaders derive
their power from God.24
Social contract theory is a view in philosophy that explains government
power by saying that it is as if all the citizens yield by contract some of their
individual rights in order to obtain the benefits of social stability available only
through a recognized government.25 It fits best in discussing democratic governments. Thomas Hobbes, cited earlier, is one of the early proponents of this
theory. It was his view that people contemplating life without government and
foreseeing a war of all against all willingly cede some of their individual liberties
in order to provide an organized check against man’s baser impulses. John Locke
was another English philosopher who held the social contract theory.26 These
two, along with several French philosophers, strongly influenced the founders
of the American government and legal system.
According to social contract theory, each of us gives up some rights to government and in return gains some rights that we would not otherwise have.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
74 Ethical Theory
Again, rights are worthless without corresponding duties. Citizens who have
agreed to give up some rights to strengthen others also take on some duties
as part of the social contract. Just as others are obliged to respect my private
property, and the state will enforce this right for me, so I must also respect
the private property of others. If the state is to provide for common defense
against aggressors, and I have a right to be defended, then I also have a duty
to provide some share of the cost of providing such defense. We buy products
or services from brokers or dealers or retailers. We buy common defense (and
other common goods) through taxes and sometimes through serving in the
government.
Obviously all citizens do not sign social contracts, individually or collectively. This view of social rights and duties is on an “as if” basis. It is sometimes
referred to as a thought experiment. It does make a certain sense as an explanation of why government has rights, why individuals are designated or elected
and have position rights as agents of government, and why government has
duties to respect and protect the rights of its citizens. Distinguishing democracy
as practiced in the United States from other forms of government, it is sometimes said that ours is a government of laws rather than of men. This means that
individuals hold government power and enforce it under the constraint of law,
and that a change in the individuals in power will not change the laws or rules
of government.27
Do legal rights have a place in a discussion of morality? As we indicated in
Chapter 3, there is a starting assumption in most moral systems that civil laws
are to be obeyed. In other words, it is moral to be legal. While this assumption
is not universally true, we will argue that it is unethical for a manager to violate
the law and cause her company to face legal penalties. Thus legal rights can and
do impose moral as well as legal obligations on companies and their managers
and employees. Note that, because we have a government of laws, when we say
that it is moral to follow the law, we are not saying that it is moral to follow the
political leader.
Position Rights
A third source of rights is position. If he has probable cause to do so, a policeman
has the right to stop a motorist, require him to get out of his car, make a physical search of his person, handcuff him, and take him to jail. These are powerful
rights. An accounts payable clerk may have authorization to spend a company’s
money without further approval up to $1,000. The chief financial officer may
have similar authority up to $100,000. A manager has the right to hire one
applicant while denying other applicants the job. She has the duty by her position as manager to do this fairly. She also has the position right to terminate an
employee for unsatisfactory performance, as well as the duty to do so. We will
explore these issues further in the second half of the book.
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 75
Again, there is some overlap between classes of rights. The policeman has
his authority by law as well as by position, but there is no law authorizing chief
financial officers or accounts payable clerks to disburse certain amounts of company funds.28 Rights by position are just that: they accrue to holders of certain
positions while they are in those positions. A former police officer does not have
arresting authority, nor does a former chief financial officer any longer have
company disbursement authority. We hope that the holders of positions granting rights have the knowledge and skills to exercise the rights appropriately, but
knowledge and skill by themselves do not carry these rights.
Positions carry duties as well as rights. Attorneys have a fiduciary duty to
their clients. Employees have a duty to carry out the responsibilities of their job.
Government officials have a duty to uphold the Constitution. Managers have a
number of duties. We will explore some of these duties in detail in the chapters
comprising the second half of this book. One individual can have multiple duties
because of the different roles that he plays in life. He can have spousal and parental duties at home, managerial duties at work, fiduciary duties as treasurer of his
church, and coaching duties as a Little League baseball coach.
According to the rights and duties approach to ethics, an individual’s actions
will be moral if they recognize the rights of others, and observe the duties
imposed on him by those rights. Everyone has a duty not to randomly kill other
people. Not everyone has a duty to prepare accounting reports in accordance
with generally accepted accounting principles, or to show up thirty minutes
early and bring the bats and balls for a youth baseball game. However, some
individuals do have these duties, and under this view of ethics, they are morally
obliged to carry them out. By becoming a manager, one takes on position rights
and duties, and ethics for managers must take this fact into account.
Contract Rights
The fourth and final source of rights is by contract. My wife has no right, as a
human, by law, or by her position, to collect $100,000 from Metropolitan Life
Insurance Company. Correspondingly, the company has no duty to pay her
this amount (or any amount) of money. However, if I purchase a life insurance
policy from Metropolitan Life, they will agree to pay my designated beneficiary
(in this case, my wife) a given amount of money if I die while the policy is in
force. The life insurance contract is what establishes the right and the duty. It is
a legally enforceable contract, but this is not a right of citizenship or a legal right
in the sense discussed above.
Contracts are formal agreements between two or more parties. The agreement
of both parties to the contract initiates rights and duties spelled out in the contract,
and they will remain in force as long as the contract is valid. This description of
how contracts work is vastly simplified, but it is not false. Contract law is extensive, well developed, and contains precedents for an extremely wide variety of
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
76 Ethical Theory
contracting situations and disputes.29 Nonetheless, the basic idea of contracts is
simple enough. It is important for the rights and duties view of ethics because
contracts create both rights and duties where none existed before, and would not
exist except for the contract. In Chapter 9 on ethics and terminations, we will see
that some people work under explicit employment contracts. The question of
whether others work under an implicit employment contract, and what rights and
duties such an implicit contract might impose, is a particularly troublesome one.
Contracts obviously play an important role in managerial ethics. Labor–
management contracts spell out the terms and conditions of employment for
employees who are covered under a collective bargaining agreement. Such
contracts typically oblige managers to pay certain wages and benefits, provide
certain working conditions, and refrain from firing employees except under
specified circumstances. Contracts may also affect relations with customers, suppliers, and other company stakeholders.
We have now seen four sources of rights and their corresponding duties.
Before we leave this subject of sources of rights, some observations are in order.
Perhaps the most fundamental is that no right is absolute. The most general or
universal rights are human rights, because they are not dependent on a given
legal system, position, or contract. The most basic of human rights is the right to
life. However, there are times when even this right does not prevail against all
other considerations. If you are actively and immediately trying to kill someone
else, a policeman is morally justified in taking your life to prevent you from
committing murder. A soldier in battle may not leave the field because he fears
for his life. Since this most basic of all rights can sometimes be over-ridden by
other considerations, it stands to reason that other rights also have less than
absolute strength. Clearly, if the most basic of all rights can be out-weighed by
other considerations, lesser rights are also subject to prioritizing. Finally, since
some rights are granted by law and others have other sources, it is clear that law
and ethics are not identical.
Kant’s Duty-Based Approach
Immanuel Kant is the philosopher most often associated with the rights and
duties approach to morality. He wrote a number of widely cited works, some
of which are difficult to read and some of which are nearly impossible. A flavor
of his approach can be obtained by reviewing some of his titles. Among his
most noted works are the Critique of Pure Reason,30 Critique of Practical Reason,31
and Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.32 While his writings are difficult, his
influence on subsequent philosophers has been great.
Kant emphasizes duties rather than rights. He identifies two kinds of rules
(he calls them “imperatives”): hypothetical and categorical. Hypothetical imperatives are conditional. If you want to be a good flute player, then you ought
to practice every day. The categorical imperative is not conditioned: it applies
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 77
always and everywhere, according to Kant. He phrases this categorical imperative in three different ways:
1.
2.
3.
Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will
that it should become a universal law.33
Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own
person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, and
never as a means.34
Therefore, every rational being must so act as if he were through his maxim
always a legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends.35
The first phrasing is perhaps the easiest to understand. Kant gives the example
of a man who borrows money, but then has difficulty coming up with enough
to pay it back. The question Kant poses is whether this individual can morally
fail or refuse to repay the borrowed money. He explains that a universal rule
that says “repay loans only if it is convenient” could not work, because no one
would lend money under such circumstances. The same sort of analysis would
apply to a rule that said “lie when it is inconvenient or embarrassing to tell the
truth.” The Categorical Imperative imposes duties on everyone, all the time.
Kant is more rigid in his interpretation of universal duties than most other
philosophers. If we consider the different kinds of rights enumerated above,
we will see that the universal duty required by the Categorical Imperative fits
best with human rights, because they are not dependent on anything else to be
applicable. One could form a universal rule to obey the tax laws of the countries where your business is conducted, but this already introduces a certain
degree of contingency. Even here, though, Kant’s approach seems to many to
be too rigid.
Suppose that I am home at night reading a novel, and my next-door neighbor knocks frantically on my door. When I open the door, she has terror in
her eyes and asks me to hide her, because her husband is trying to kill her. I
tell her to hurry upstairs and go in the room to the right. One minute later, her
husband pounds on my door. When I open it, he is holding a gun and asks me
where his wife is, because he wants to kill her. Is the moral answer “Upstairs to
the right”? Most people would say not. This brings us back to the point made
earlier: that no right is absolute. His right to be told the truth is not as great as
her right to life.
This seemingly simple example has profound consequences. Since we have
established one time when it is moral to lie and immoral to tell the truth, we
must at some point enter the swamp of real life and sort out when else it might
be moral to lie. While something like the Categorical Imperative has a certain conceptual attractiveness to many people because of its simplicity and its
message of universal duties, in the real world where managers make decisions,
simple universal rules do not always work. In other words, real-life rules for
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
78 Ethical Theory
morality cannot be simple and universal. From this it does not follow that everything is always up for negotiation. It does follow, though, that some decisions
will not be easy to sort out from a moral point of view, and that the comfort
of certainty may not always be obtainable. We will examine some examples of
cases where lying might be permissible in the following chapters.
General Observations
Another general point about the rights and duties approach to ethics is that it is
not completely different from the utilitarian approach. One could argue that we
have a duty to perform those actions that will result in the greatest good for the
greatest number of people. However, the emphases of the two approaches are
notably different. Utilitarianism focuses on the results of actions, and determines
their morality by calculating those results (or a prediction of them). Rights and
duties call attention to obligations to act in a certain way. These obligations do
not arise from the projected results of our actions but from intrinsic rights or
duties. One other general point about the rights and duties approach to morality
should be noted. There are important areas of life and human relations where
this approach is not enough, or perhaps sometimes even appropriate. Family life
is one such area. If a husband and wife, or mother and child deal with each other
on the basis of rights and duties, the relationship will lack important elements
that ought to be present. Certainly the rights and duties approach has something
to say about family relationships. Each spouse does have a right to some time
alone, or to pursue their own interests, and children do have some rights (as they
are quick to remind parents). Laws govern the property rights of each spouse,
and parents have a legal obligation not to neglect their children. However, the
love that motivates spouses and parents is really not captured in a discussion of
rights and duties.
Churches and religious organizations have rights and duties regarding their
members, but again this is not the kind of discussion that captures the actions
and relationships of pastors and church members most of the time. Volunteer
groups of many kinds use the time and skill of members. Boy scouts and girl
scouts, youth sports activities, and homeless centers all flourish largely because
individuals are willing to give their time and talent without employment relations or direct compensation. Again, some basic rights and duties do exist, but
this form of discussion does not begin to capture the full scope of human relations that exists in volunteer groups. Even in work situations, it is not rights and
duties that causes people to organize potluck luncheons or take up a collection
for a co-worker about to get married.
In the workplace, where managers have specific roles to play, rights and
duties often provide an appropriate language and set of concepts for thinking
about the morality of actions. The whole stakeholder approach to business deals
EBSCOhost - printed on 4/3/2022 11:21 PM via UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND GLOBAL CAMPUS. All use subject to https://www.ebsco.com/terms-of-use
Rights and Duties 79
with issues of what individuals or groups that affect or are affected by organizations have rights or duties with regard to those organizations. Within the
organization, managers have duties both to their bosses and to their sub...
Purchase answer to see full
attachment