Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness
Preservation: A Third World Critique
by Ramachandra Guha
This essay is from Environmental Ethics, Vol. 11, No.1 (Spring
1989), 71-83. Guha is an ecologist at the Centre for Ecological
Sciences, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore 560 012, India. He
wrote the essay during a visiting lecturership at the Yale School of
Forestry and Environmental Studies.
I. Introduction
The respected radical journalist Kirkpatrick Sale
recently celebrated “the passion of a new and growing
movement that has become disenchanted with the
environmental establishment and has in recent years
mounted a serious and sweeping attack on it—style,
substance, systems, sensibilities and all.”l The vision
of those whom Sale calls the “New Ecologists”—and
what I refer to in this article as deep ecology—is a
compelling one. Decrying the narrowly economic
goals of mainstream environmentalism, this new
movement aims at nothing less than a philosophical
and cultural revolution in human attitudes toward
nature. In contrast to the conventional lobbying efforts
of environmental professionals based in Washington,
it proposes a militant defence of “Mother Earth,” an
unflinching opposition to human attacks on
undisturbed wilderness. With their goals ranging from
the spiritual to the political, the adherents of deep
ecology span a wide spectrum of the American
environmental movement. As Sale correctly notes, this
emerging strand has in a matter of a few years made
its presence felt in a number of fields: from academic
philosophy (as in the journal Environmental Ethics) to
popular environmentalism (for example, the group
Earth First!).
terms. I make two main arguments: first, that deep
ecology is uniquely American, and despite superficial
similarities in rhetorical style, the social and political
goals of radical environmentalism in other cultural
contexts (e.g., West Germany and India) are quite
different; second, that the social consequences of
putting deep ecology into practice on a worldwide
basis (what its practitioners are aiming for) are very
grave indeed.
II. The Tenets of Deep Ecology
While I am aware that the term deep ecology was
coined by the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess, this
article refers specifically to the American variant.2
Adherents of the deep ecological perspective in this
country, while arguing intensely among themselves
over its political and philosophical implications, share
some fundamental premises about human-nature
interactions. As I see it, the defining characteristics of
deep ecology are fourfold.
In this article I develop a critique of deep ecology
from the perspective of a sympathetic outsider. I
critique deep ecology not as a general (or even a foot
soldier) in the continuing struggle between the ghosts
of Gifford Pinchot and John Muir over control of the
U.S. environmental movement, but as an outsider to
these battles. I speak admittedly as a partisan, but of
the environmental movement in India, a country with
an ecological diversity comparable to the U.S., but
with a radically dissimilar cultural and social history.
First, deep ecology argues that the environmental
movement must shift from an “anthropocentric” to a
“biocentric” perspective. In many respects, an
acceptance of the primacy of this distinction
constitutes the litmus test of deep ecology. A
considerable effort is expended by deep ecologists in
showing that the dominant motif in Western
philosophy has been anthropocentric—i.e., the belief
that man and his works are the center of the
universe—and conversely, in identifying those lonely
thinkers (Leopold, Thoreau, Muir, Aldous Huxley,
Santayana, etc.) who, in assigning man a more humble
place in the natural order, anticipated deep ecological
thinking. In the political realm, meanwhile,
establishment environmentalism (shallow ecology) is
chided for casting its arguments in human-centered
terms. Preserving nature, the deep ecologists say, has
an intrinsic worth quite apart from any benefits
preservation may convey to future human generations.
The anthropocentric-biocentric distinction is accepted
as axiomatic by deep ecologists, it structures their
discourse, and much of the present discussions
remains mired within it.
My treatment of deep ecology is primarily historical
and sociological, rather than philosophical, in nature.
Specifically, I examine the cultural rootedness of a
philosophy that likes to present itself in universalistic
The second characteristic of deep ecology is its focus
on the preservation of unspoilt wilderness and the
restoration of degraded areas to a more pristine
condition—to the relative (and sometimes absolute)
1
neglect of other issues on the environmental agenda. I
later identify the cultural roots and portentous
consequences of this obsession with wilderness. For
the moment, let me indicate three distinct sources
from which it springs. Historically, it represents a
playing out of the preservationist (read radical) and
utilitarian (read reformist) dichotomy that has plagued
American environmentalism since the turn of the
century. Morally, it is an imperative that follows from
the biocentric perspective; other species of plants and
animals, and nature itself, have an intrinsic right to
exist. And finally, the preservation of wilderness also
turns on a scientific argument—viz., the value of
biological diversity in stabilizing ecological regimes
and in retaining a gene pool for future generations.
Truly radical policy proposals have been put forward
by deep ecologists on the basis of these arguments.
The influential poet Gary Snyder, for example, would
like to see a 90 percent reduction in human
populations to allow a restoration of pristine
environments, while others have argued forcefully that
a large portion of the globe must be immediately
cordoned off from human beings.3
Third, there is a widespread invocation of Eastern
spiritual traditions as forerunners of deep ecology.
Deep ecology, it is suggested, was practiced both by
major religious traditions and at a more popular level
by “primal” peoples in non-Western settings. This
complements the search for an authentic lineage in
Western thought. At one level, the task is to recover
those dissenting voices within the Judeo-Christian
tradition; at another, to suggest that religious traditions
in other cultures are, in contrast, dominantly if not
exclusively “biocentric” in their orientation. This
coupling of (ancient) Eastern and (modern) ecological
wisdom seemingly helps consolidate the claim that
deep ecology is a philosophy of universal significance.
Fourth, deep ecologists, whatever their internal
differences, share the belief that they are the “leading
edge” of the environmental movement. As the polarity
of the shallow / deep and anthropocentric / biocentric
distinctions makes clear, they see themselves as the
spiritual, philosophical, and political vanguard of
American and world environmentalism.
III. Toward a Critique
Although I analyze each of these tenets independently,
it is important to recognize, as deep ecologists are
fond of remarking in reference to nature, the
interconnectedness and unity of these individual
themes.
(1) Insofar as it has begun to act as a check on man’s
arrogance and ecological hubris, the transition from an
anthropocentric (human-centered) to a biocentric
(humans as only one element in the ecosystem) view
in both religious and scientific traditions is only to be
welcomed.4 What is unacceptable are the radical
conclusions drawn by deep ecology, in particular, that
intervention in nature should be guided primarily by
the need to preserve biotic integrity rather than by the
needs of humans. The latter for deep ecologists is
anthropocentric, the former biocentric. This
dichotomy is, however, of very little use in
understanding the dynamics of environmental
degradation. The two fundamental ecological
problems facing the globe are (i) overconsumption by
the industrialized world and by urban elites in the
Third World and (ii) growing militarization, both in a
short-term sense (i.e., ongoing regional wars) and in a
long-term sense (i.e., the arms race and the prospect of
nuclear annihilation). Neither of these problems has
any tangible connection to the anthropocentricbiocentric distinction. Indeed, the agents of these
processes would barely comprehend this philosophical
dichotomy. The proximate causes of the ecologically
wasteful characteristics of industrial society and of
militarization are far more mundane: at an aggregate
level, the dialectic of economic and political
structures, and at a micro-level, the life-style choices
of individuals. These causes cannot be reduced,
whatever the level of analysis, to a deeper
anthropocentric attitude toward nature; on the
contrary, by constituting a grave threat to human
survival, the ecological degradation they cause does
not even serve the best interests of human beings! If
my identification of the major dangers to the integrity
of the natural world is correct, invoking the bogy of
anthropocentricism is at best irrelevant and at worst a
dangerous obfuscation.
(2) If the above dichotomy is irrelevant, the emphasis
on wilderness is positively harmful when applied to
the Third World. If in the U.S. the preservationist /
utilitarian division is seen as mirroring the conflict
between “people” and “interests,” in countries such as
India the situation is very nearly the reverse. Because
India is a long settled and densely populated country
in which agrarian populations have a finely balanced
relationship with nature, the setting aside of
wilderness areas has resulted in a direct transfer of
resources from the poor to the rich. Thus, Project
Tiger, a network of parks hailed by the international
conservation community as an outstanding success,
sharply posits the interests of the tiger against those of
poor peasants living in and around the reserve. The
designation of tiger reserves was made possible only
by the physical displacement of existing villages and
their inhabitants; their management requires the
continuing exclusion of peasants and livestock. The
initial impetus for setting up parks for the tiger and
2
other large mammals such as the rhinoceros and
elephant came from two social groups, first, a class of
ex-hunters turned conservationists belonging mostly
to the declining Indian feudal elite and second,
representatives of international agencies, such as the
World Wildlife Fund (WWF) and the International
Union for the Conservation of Nature and Natural
Resources (IUCN), seeking to transplant the American
system of national parks onto Indian soil. In no case
have the needs of the local population been taken into
account, and as in many parts of Africa, the
designated wildlands are managed primarily for the
benefit of rich tourists. Until very recently, wildlands
preservation has been identified with
environmentalism by the state and the conservation
elite; in consequence, environmental problems that
impinge far more directly on the lives of the poor—
e.g., fuel, fodder, water shortages, soil erosion, and air
and water pollution—have not been adequately
addressed.5
Deep ecology provides, perhaps unwittingly, a
justification for the continuation of such narrow and
inequitable conservation practices under a newly
acquired radical guise. Increasingly, the international
conservation elite is using the philosophical, moral,
and scientific arguments used by deep ecologists in
advancing their wilderness crusade. A striking but by
no means atypical example is the recent plea by a
prominent American biologist for the takeover of
large portions of the globe by the author and his
scientific colleagues. Writing in a prestigious
scientific forum, the Annual Review of Ecology and
Systematics, Daniel Janzen argues that only biologists
have the competence to decide how the tropical
landscape should be used. As “the representatives of
the natural world,” biologists are “in charge of the
future of tropical ecology,” and only they have the
expertise and mandate to “determine whether the
tropical agroscape is to be populated only by humans,
their mutualists, commensals, and parasites, or
whether it will also contain some islands of the greater
nature—the nature that spawned humans, yet has been
vanquished by them.” Janzen exhorts his colleagues to
advance their territorial claims on the tropical world
more forcefully, warning that the very existence of
these areas is at stake: “if biologists want a tropics in
which to biologize, they are going to have to buy it
with care, energy, effort, strategy, tactics, time, and
cash.”6
This frankly imperialist manifesto highlights the
multiple dangers of the preoccupation with wilderness
preservation that is characteristic of deep ecology. As
I have suggested, it seriously compounds the neglect
by the American movement of far more pressing
environmental problems within the Third World. But
perhaps more importantly, and in a more insidious
fashion, it also provides an impetus to the imperialist
yearning of Western biologists and their financial
sponsors, organizations such as the WWF and IUCN.
The wholesale transfer of a movement culturally
rooted in American conservation history can only
result in the social uprooting of human populations in
other parts of the globe.
(3) I come now to the persistent invocation of Eastern
philosophies as antecedent in point of time but
convergent in their structure with deep ecology.
Complex and internally differentiated religious
traditions—Hinduism, Buddhism, and Taoism—are
lumped together as holding a view of nature believed
to be quintessentially biocentric. Individual
philosophers such as the Taoist Lao Tzu are identified
as being forerunners of deep ecology. Even an
intensely political, pragmatic, and Christianinfluenced thinker such as Gandhi has been accorded a
wholly undeserved place in the deep ecological
pantheon. Thus the Zen teacher Robert Aitken Roshi
makes the strange claim that Gandhi’s thought was not
human-centered and that he practiced an embryonic
form of deep ecology which is “traditionally Eastern
and is found with differing emphasis in Hinduism,
Taoism and in Theravada and Mahayana Buddhism.”7
Moving away from the realm of high philosophy and
scriptural religion, deep ecologists make the further
claim that at the level of material and spiritual practice
“primal” peoples subordinated themselves to the
integrity of the biotic universe they inhabited.
I have indicated that this appropriation of Eastern
traditions is in part dictated by the need to construct an
authentic lineage and in part a desire to present deep
ecology as a universalistic philosophy. Indeed, in his
substantial and quixotic biography of John Muir,
Michael Cohen goes so far as to suggest that Muir was
the “Taoist of the [American] West.”8 This reading of
Eastern traditions is selective and does not bother to
differentiate between alternate (and changing)
religious and cultural traditions; as it stands, it does
considerable violence to the historical record.
Throughout most recorded history the characteristic
form of human activity in the “East” has been a finely
tuned but nonetheless conscious and dynamic
manipulation of nature. Although mystics such as Lao
Tzu did reflect on the spiritual essence of human
relations with nature, it must be recognized that such
ascetics and their reflections were supported by a
society of cultivators whose relationship with nature
was a far more active one. Many agricultural
communities do have a sophisticated knowledge of the
natural environment that may equal (and sometimes
surpass) codified “scientific” knowledge; yet, the
elaboration of such traditional ecological knowledge
3
(in both material and spiritual contexts) can hardly be
said to rest on a mystical affinity with nature of a deep
ecological kind. Nor is such knowledge infallible; as
the archaeological record powerfully suggests, modern
Western man has no monopoly on ecological
disasters.
In a brilliant article, the Chicago historian Ronald
Inden points out that this romantic and essentially
positive view of the East is a mirror image of the
scientific and essentially pejorative view normally
upheld by Western scholars of the Orient. In either
case, the East constitutes the Other, a body wholly
separate and alien from the West; it is defined by a
uniquely spiritual and nonrational “essence,” even if
this essence is valorized quite differently by the two
schools. Eastern man exhibits a spiritual dependence
with respect to nature—the one hand, this is
symptomatic of his prescientific and backward self, on
the other, of his ecological wisdom and deep
ecological consciousness. Both views are monolithic,
simplistic, and have the characteristic effect—
intended in one case, perhaps unintended in the
other—of denying agency and reason to the East and
making it the privileged orbit of Western thinkers.
The two apparently opposed perspectives have then a
common underlying structure of discourse in which
the East merely serves as a vehicle for Western
projections. Varying images of the East are raw
material for political and cultural battles being played
out in the West; they tell us far more about the
Western commentator and his desires than about the
“East.” Inden’s remarks apply not merely to Western
scholarship on India, but to Orientalist constructions
of China and Japan as well.
Although these two views appear to be strongly
opposed, they often combine together. Both
have a similar interest in sustaining the
Otherness of India. The holders of the
dominant view, best exemplified in the past in
imperial administrative discourse (and today
probably by that of ‘development economics’),
would place a traditional, superstition-ridden
India in a position of perpetual tutelage to a
modern, rational West. The adherents of the
romantic view, best exemplified academically
in the discourses of Christian liberalism and
analytic psychology, concede the realm of the
public and impersonal to the positivist. Taking
their succor not from governments and big
business, but from a plethora of religious
foundations and self-help institutes, and from
allies in the ‘consciousness’ industry, not to
mention the important industry of tourism, the
romantics insist that India embodies a private
realm of the imagination and the religious
which modern, western man lacks but needs.
They, therefore, like the positivists, but for just
the opposite reason, have a vested interest in
seeing that the Orientalist view of India as
‘spiritual,’ ‘mysterious,’ and ‘exotic’ is
perpetuated.9
(4) How radical, finally, are the deep ecologists?
Notwithstanding their self-image and strident rhetoric
(in which the label “shallow ecology” has an
opprobrium similar to that reserved for “social
democratic” by Marxist-Leninists), even within the
American context their radicalism is limited and it
manifests itself quite differently elsewhere.
To my mind, deep ecology is best viewed as a radical
trend within the wilderness preservation movement.
Although advancing philosophical rather than
aesthetic arguments and encouraging political
militancy rather than negotiation, its practical
emphasis—viz., preservation of unspoilt nature—is
virtually identical. For the mainstream movement, the
function of wilderness is to provide a temporary
antidote to modern civilization. As a special institution
within an industrialized society, the national park
“provides an opportunity for respite, contrast,
contemplation, and affirmation of values for those
who live most of their lives in the workaday world.”10
Indeed, the rapid increase in visitations to the national
parks in postwar America is a direct consequence of
economic expansion. The emergence of a popular
interest in wilderness sites, the historian Samuel Hays
points out, was “not a throwback to the primitive, but
an integral part of the modern standard of living as
people sought to add new ‘amenity’ and ‘aesthetic’
goals and desires to their earlier preoccupation with
necessities and conveniences.”11
Here, the enjoyment of nature is an integral part of the
consumer society. The private automobile (and the life
style it has spawned) is in many respects the ultimate
ecological villain, and an untouched wilderness the
prototype of ecological harmony; yet, for most
Americans it is perfectly consistent to drive a
thousand miles to spend a holiday in a national park.
They possess a vast, beautiful, and sparsely populated
continent and are also able to draw upon the natural
resources of large portions of the globe by virtue of
their economic and political dominance. In
consequence, America can simultaneously enjoy the
material benefits of an expanding economy and the
aesthetic benefits of unspoilt nature. The two poles of
“wilderness” and “civilization” mutually coexist in an
internally coherent whole, and philosophers of both
poles are assigned a prominent place in this culture.
Paradoxically as it may seem, it is no accident that
4
Star Wars technology and deep ecology both find their
fullest expression in that leading sector of Western
civilization, California.
Deep ecology runs parallel to the consumer society
without seriously questioning its ecological and sociopolitical basis. In its celebration of American
wilderness, it also displays an uncomfortable
convergence with the prevailing climate of
nationalism in the American wilderness movement.
For spokesmen such as the historian Roderick Nash,
the national park system is America’s distinctive
cultural contribution to the world, reflective not
merely of its economic but of its philosophical and
ecological maturity as well. In what Walter Lippman
called the American century, the “American invention
of national parks” must be exported worldwide.
Betraying an economic determinism that would make
even a Marxist shudder, Nash believes that
environmental preservation is a “full stomach”
phenomenon that is confined to the rich, urban, and
sophisticated. Nonetheless, he hopes that “the less
developed nations may eventually evolve
economically and intellectually to the point where
nature preservation is more than a business.”12
The error which Nash makes (and which deep ecology
in some respects encourages) is to equate
environmental protection with the protection of
wilderness. This is a distinctively American notion,
borne out of a unique social and environmental
history. The archetypal concerns of radical
environmentalists in other cultural contexts are in fact
quite different. The German Greens, for example,
have elaborated a devastating critique of industrial
society which turns on the acceptance of
environmental limits to growth. Pointing to the
intimate links between industrialization, militarization,
and conquest, the Greens argue that economic growth
in the West has historically rested on the economic
and ecological exploitation of the Third World. Rudolf
Bahro is characteristically blunt:
The working class here [in the West] is the
richest lower class in the world. And if I look
at the problem from the point of view of the
whole of humanity, not just from that of
Europe, then I must say that the metropolitan
working class is the worst exploiting class in
history. ...What made poverty bearable in
eighteenth- or nineteenth-century Europe was
the prospect of escaping it through exploitation
of the periphery. But this is no longer a
possibility, and continued industrialism in the
Third World will mean poverty for whole
generations and hunger for millions.13
Here the roots of global ecological problems lie in the
disproportionate share of resources consumed by the
industrialized countries as a whole and the urban elite
within the Third World. Since it is impossible to
reproduce an industrial monoculture worldwide, the
ecological movement in the West must begin by
cleaning up its own act. The Greens advocate the
creation of a “no growth” economy, to be achieved by
scaling down current (and clearly unsustainable)
consumption levels)14 This radical shift in
consumption and production patterns requires the
creation of alternate economic and political
structures—smaller in scale and more amenable to
social participation—but it rests equally on a shift in
cultural values. The expansionist character of modern
Western man will have to give way to an ethic of
renunciation and self-limitation, in which spiritual and
communal values play an increasing role in sustaining
social life. This revolution in cultural values, however,
has as its point of departure an understanding of
environmental processes quite different from deep
ecology.
Many elements of the Green program find a strong
resonance in countries such as India, where a history
of Western colonialism and industrial development
has benefited only a tiny elite while exacting
tremendous social and environmental costs. The
ecological battles presently being fought in India have
as their epicenter the conflict over nature between the
subsistence and largely rural sector and the vastly
more powerful commercial-industrial sector. Perhaps
the most celebrated of these battles concerns the
Chipko (Hug the Tree) movement, a peasant
movement against deforestation in the Himalayan
foothills. Chipko is only one of several movements
that have sharply questioned the nonsustainable
demand being placed on the land and vegetative base
by urban centers and industry. These include
opposition to large dams by displaced peasants, the
conflict between small artisan fishing and large-scale
trawler fishing for export, the countrywide movements
against commercial forest operations, and opposition
to industrial pollution among downstream agricultural
and fishing communities.15
Two features distinguish these environmental
movements from their Western counterparts. First, for
the sections of society most critically affected by
environmental degradation—poor and landless
peasants, women, and tribals—it is a question of sheer
survival, not of enhancing the quality of life. Second,
and as a consequence, the environmental solutions
they articulate deeply involve questions of equity as
well as economic and political redistribution.
Highlighting these differences, a leading Indian
environmentalist stresses that “environmental
5
protection per se is of least concern to most of these
groups. Their main concern is about the use of the
environment and who should benefit from it.”16 They
seek to wrest control of nature away from the state and
the industrial sector and place it in the hands of rural
communities who live within that environment but are
increasingly denied access to it. These communities
have far more basic needs, their demands on the
environment are far less intense, and they can draw
upon a reservoir of cooperative social institutions and
local ecological knowledge in managing the
“commons”—forests, grasslands, and the waters—on
a sustainable basis. If colonial and capitalist expansion
has both accentuated social inequalities and signaled a
precipitous fall in ecological wisdom, an alternate
ecology must rest on an alternate society and polity as
well.
This brief overview of German and Indian
environmentalism has some major implications for
deep ecology. Both German and Indian environmental
traditions allow for a greater integration of ecological
concerns with livelihood and work. They also place a
greater emphasis on equity and social justice (both
within individual countries and on a global scale) on
the grounds that in the absence of social regeneration
environmental regeneration has very little chance of
succeeding, Finally, and perhaps most significantly,
they have escaped the preoccupation with wilderness
preservation so characteristic of American cultural and
environmental history.17
IV. A Homily
In 1958, the economist J. K. Galbraith referred to
overconsumption as the unasked question of the
American conservation movement. There is a marked
selectivity, he wrote, “in the conservationist’s
approach to materials consumption. If we are
concerned about our great appetite for materials, it is
plausible to seek to increase the supply, to decrease
waste, to make better use of the stocks available, and
to develop substitutes. But what of the appetite itself?
Surely this is the ultimate source of the problem. If it
continues its geometric course, will it not one day
have to be restrained? Yet in the literature of the
resource problem this is the forbidden question. Over
it hangs a nearly total silence.”18
The consumer economy and society have expanded
tremendously in the three decades since Galbraith
penned these words; yet his criticisms are nearly as
valid today. I have said “nearly,” for there are some
hopeful signs. Within the environmental movement
several dispersed groups are working to develop
ecologically benign technologies and to encourage
less wasteful life styles. Moreover, outside the self-
defined boundaries of American environmentalism,
opposition to the permanent war economy is being
carried on by a peace movement that has a
distinguished history and impeccable moral and
political credentials.
It is precisely these (to my mind, most hopeful)
components of the American social scene that are
missing from deep ecology. In their widely noticed
book, Bill Devall and George Sessions make no
mention of militarization or the movements for peace,
while activists whose practical focus is on developing
ecologically responsible life styles (e.g., Wendell
Berry) are derided as “falling short of deep ecological
awareness.”19 A truly radical ecology in the American
context ought to work toward a synthesis of the
appropriate technology, alternate life style, and peace
movements.20 By making the (largely spurious)
anthropocentric-biocentric distinction central to the
debate, deep ecologists may have appropriated the
moral high ground, but they are at the same time
doing a serious disservice to American and global
environmentalism.21
Notes
1. Kirkpatrick Sale, “The Forest for the Trees: Can Today’s
Environmentalists Tell the Difference,” Mother Jones 11,
No.8 (November 1986): 26.
2. One of the major criticisms I make in this essay concerns
deep ecology’s lack of concern with inequalities within
human society. In the article in which he coined the term
deep ecology, Naess himself expresses concerns about
inequalities between and within nations. However, his
concern with social cleavages and their impact on resource
utilization patterns and ecological destruction is not very
visible in the later writings of deep ecologists. See Arne
Naess, “The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology
Movement: A Summary,” Inquiry 16 (1973): 96 (I am
grateful to Tom Birch for this reference).
3. Gary Snyder, quoted in Sale, “The Forest for the Trees,”
p. 32. See also Dave Foreman, “ A Modest Proposal for a
Wilderness System,” Whole Earth Review, no.53 (Winter
1986-87): 42-45.
4. See, for example, Donald Worster, Nature’s Economy:
The Roots of Ecology (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books,
1977).
5. See Centre for Science and Environment, India: The State
of the Environment 1982: A Citizens Report (New Delhi:
Centre for Science and Environment, 1982); R. Sukumar,
“Elephant-Man Conflict in Karnataka,” in Cecil Saldanha,
ed., The State of Karnataka’s Environment (Bangalore:
Centre for Taxonomic Studies, 1985). For Africa, see the
brilliant analysis by Helge Kjekshus, Ecology Control and
Economic Development in East African History (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1977).
6. Daniel Janzen, “The Future of Tropical Ecology,” Annual
Review of Ecology and Systematics 17 (1986): 305-06;
emphasis added.
6
7. Robert Aitken Roshi, “Gandhi, Dogen, and Deep
Ecology,” reprinted as appendix C in Bill Devall and George
Sessions, Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered (Salt
Lake City: Peregrine Smith Books, 1985). For Gandhi’s own
views on social reconstruction, see the excellent threevolume collection edited by Raghavan Iyer, The Moral and
Political Writings of Mahatma Gandhi (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1986-87).
8. Michael Cohen, The Pathless Way (Madison: University
of Wisconsin Press, 1984), p. 120.
9. Ronald Inden, “Orientalist Constructions of India,”
Modern Asian Studies 20 (1986): 442. Inden draws
inspiration from Edward Said’s forceful polemic,
Orientalism (New York: Basic Books, 1980). It must be
noted, however, that there is a salient difference between
Western perceptions of Middle Eastern and Far Eastern
cultures, respectively. Due perhaps to the long history of
Christian conflict with Islam, Middle Eastern cultures (as
Said documents) are consistently presented in pejorative
terms. The juxtaposition of hostile and worshiping attitudes
that Inden talks of applies only to Western attitudes toward
Buddhist and Hindu societies.
10. Joseph Sax, Mountains Without Handrails: Reflections
on the National Parks (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press, 1980), p. 42. Cf. also Peter Schmitt, Back to Nature:
The Arcadian Myth in Urban America (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1969), and Alfred Runte, National Parks:
The American Experience (Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press, 1979).
11. Samuel Hays, “From Conservation to Environment:
Environmental Politics in the United States since World War
Two,” Environmental Review 6 (1982): 21. See also the
same authors book entitled Beauty, Health and Permanence:
Environmental Politics in the United States, 1955-85 (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
12. Roderick Nash, Wilderness and the American Mind, 3rd
ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982).
13. Rudolf Bahro, From Red to Green (London: Verso
Books, 1984).
14. From time to time, American scholars have themselves
criticized these imbalances in consumption patterns. In the
1950s, William Vogt made the charge that the United States,
with one-sixteenth of the world’s population, was utilizing
one-third of the globe’s resources. (Vogt, cited in E. F.
Murphy, Nature, Bureaucracy and the Rule of Property
[Amsterdam: North Holland, 1977 p. 29]). More recently,
Zero Population Growth has estimated that each American
consumes thirty-nine times as many resources as an Indian.
See Christian Science Monitor, 2 March 1987.
15. For an excellent review, see Anil Agarwal and Sunita
Narain, eds., India: The State of the Environment 1984-85: A
Citizens Report (New Delhi: Centre for Science and
Environment, 1985). Cf. also Ramachandra Guha, The
Unquiet Woods: Ecological Change and Peasant Resistance
in the Indian Himalaya (Berkeley: University of California
Press, forthcoming).
16. Anil Agarwal, “Human-Nature Interactions in a Third
World Country,” The Environmentalist 6, no.3 (1986): 167.
17. One strand in radical American environmentalism, the
bioregional movement, by emphasizing a greater
involvement with the bioregion people inhabit, does
indirectly challenge consumerism. However, as yet
bioregionalism has hardly raised the questions of equity and
social justice (international, intranational, and
intergenerational), which I argue must be a central plank of
radical environmentalism. Moreover, its stress on
(individual) experience as the key to involvement with
nature is also somewhat at odds with the integration of
nature with livelihood and work that I talk of in this paper.
Cf. Kirkpatrick Sale, Dwellers in the Land: The Bioregional
Vision (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1985).
18. John Kenneth Galbraith, “How Much Should a Country
Consume?” in Henry Jarrett, ed., Perspectives on
Conservation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1958), pp.
91-92.
19. Devall and Sessions, Deep Ecology, p. 122. For Wendell
Berry’s own assessment of deep ecology, see his
“Amplications: Preserving Wildness,” Wilderness 50
(Spring 1987): 39-40, 50-54.
20. See the interesting recent contribution by one of the
most influential spokesmen of appropriate technology—
Barry Commoner, “ A Reporter at Large: The
Environment,” New Yorker, 15 June 1987. While
Commoner makes a forceful plea for the convergence of the
environmental movement (viewed by him primarily as the
opposition to air and water pollution and to the institutions
that generate such pollution) and the peace movement, he
significantly does not mention consumption patterns,
implying that “limits to growth” do not exist.
21. In this sense, my critique of deep ecology, although that
of an outsider, may facilitate the reassertion of those
elements in the American environmental tradition for which
there is a profound sympathy in other parts of the globe. A
global perspective may also lead to a critical reassessment of
figures such as Aldo Leopold and John Muir, the two patron
saints of deep ecology. As Donald Worster has pointed out,
the message of Muir (and, I would argue, of Leopold as
well) makes sense only in an American context; he has very
little to say to other cultures. See Worster’s review of
Stephen Fox’s John Muir and His Legacy, in Environmental
Ethics 5 (1983): 277-81.
7
Our household is committed to reducing our environmental impact through recycling, conserving
electricity, and avoiding fast fashion purchases. These actions aim to minimize waste, preserve
resources, and reduce our contribution to overconsumption and environmental harm. Electricity
use, in particular, stands out as a significant issue for us, and we will focus on thoughtful usage
of appliances and lighting. Avoiding fast fashion is another key step, as it helps us lessen our
support for resource-intensive production and wasteful consumer habits.
The article I chose for my paper is Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness
Preservation: A Third World Critique by Ramachandra Guha. Reflecting on Guha’s critique, I
now see how his arguments refine and challenge certain ideas within the deep ecology
movement. Guha critiques deep ecology’s focus on opposing anthropocentrism, arguing instead
that the key drivers of environmental degradation are overconsumption and militarization. These
issues are more pressing than a strict focus on reducing human-centered perspectives or
prioritizing wilderness preservation. Guha emphasizes a more holistic approach, which aligns
closely with my personal environmental goals.
Recycling in our household helps address the overconsumption that Guha highlights. By limiting
the waste we send to landfills and reducing the demand for raw materials, recycling becomes a
practical way to counter resource depletion. This approach respects Guha’s argument that
solutions should consider everyday human needs alongside environmental preservation, rather
than focusing narrowly on wilderness protection.
Conserving electricity is another step toward combating overconsumption. By reducing our
home energy use, we directly address the strain that overuse places on power grids and
ecosystems. Guha’s critique also reminds us that environmentalism must consider fairness and
practicality—solutions should be accessible and beneficial to all communities, rather than
idealized or exclusionary.
Finally, avoiding fast fashion reflects Guha’s criticism of consumerism. Fast fashion epitomizes
the wastefulness and exploitation of environmental resources that Guha opposes. By shifting to
sustainable, long-lasting clothing, my household takes a conscious stand against unsustainable
production and waste. This choice also reflects Guha’s call for environmental actions that
integrate economic and social justice, ensuring they respect both human and non-human life.
In conclusion, my household’s efforts align with Guha’s broader critique of overconsumption
and resource exploitation. By integrating his emphasis on holistic solutions and social equity, our
actions represent small but meaningful steps toward respecting nature and fostering sustainable
living.
Purchase answer to see full
attachment