International Studies Perspectives (2011) 12, 94–118.
History, International Relations, and
Integrated Approaches: Thinking about
Greater Interdisciplinarity
Steve Yetiv
Old Dominion University
This essay starts by exploring how history can contribute to the discipline
of international relations (IR). It then moves beyond this question to
explore a broader question, beyond IR and history, with which this symposium is concerned: how can we enhance interdisciplinary analysis in
international studies? With regard to the first question, this essay
advances several themes. First, while history can serve IR in several ways,
it is especially salient to the study of change in IR. Second, the study of
history can help us connect the dots across time in ways that can complement IR. Stringing detailed cases together or examining the broader
sweep of a longer time period may help us discern causal connections
that would have been buried in more streamlined and short-term analyses. Third, history can aid in theory-building, modeling, and testing in
the study of IR. Quantitative approaches can also benefit from in-depth
historical studies. In assessing the value of history to IR, however, it is
critical to ask what type of historians and IR scholars we are considering
and to be aware of the differences among them. Fourth, while it is useful
to draw on history for IR, history also has its limits and may be misused.
At the core, this essay examines how history can contribute to IR, but
that analysis raises a broader question: how can we integrate notions and
insights from various disciplines in international studies, including history and IR? This essay advances one schema for doing so, which it calls
‘‘integrated approaches.’’ It demonstrates one type of integrated
approach for the study of foreign policy behavior. The approach systematically draws on multiple disciplines to explain behaviors such as
decisions to make treaties, go to war, or ally with other countries.
Keywords: international relations, history, interdisciplinary,
integrated approach, foreign policy
How can history contribute to international relations (IR)? This question is long
standing and has been addressed by various scholars. In fact, the question of
how to incorporate history has been salient in various fields including ‘‘historical
sociology’’ (see Clemens 2007; Hobson and Lawson 2008), ‘‘historical anthropology,’’ ‘‘historical geography,’’ and ‘‘historical economics.’’1
This essay starts by exploring how history can contribute to IR. It then
examines a larger question: how can we enhance interdisciplinary work in
international studies (IS)?
1
The last of these is perhaps most prominently on display in recent times by Ferguson (2003) who, to illustrate
the point, is both a professor of history and business, and uses history to inform modern world politics.
doi: 10.1111/j.1528-3585.2011.00422.x
2011 International Studies Association
Steve Yetiv
95
This article advances several themes. First, while history can serve IR in several
ways, I argue that history is especially important for understanding change. It
seeks to show where the work of historians and others conducting historical
work can further benefit the field of IR in its efforts to understand and theorize
about change. History is useful for exploring change across shorter or longer
time periods and can complement comparative work, especially in terms of
comparison across time.
Second, history can help reveal possible causal links across time in ways that
can complement IR. Stringing detailed cases together or examining the broader
sweep of a longer time period may help us discern causal connections that
otherwise would have been buried in more streamlined and short-term analyses.
Third, as a partial result of the foregoing points, history can aid in theorybuilding, modeling, and testing in IR. We need IR theorists who privilege
abstraction in the purist sense of the term, but we also need to encourage more
work in IR that is both theory- and historically oriented. Those who do both history and IR in the field of IR are sometimes caught in the ‘‘under-privileged’’
center, but they play an important bridging role between the ‘‘pure’’ theorists
and the ‘‘pure’’ empiricists. The value of history is not limited to the work of
IR positivists. History can also benefit non-positivist work in the field of international relations, such as in some areas of constructivism and postmodernism. In
assessing the value of history to IR, however, we need to inquire about the type
of historians and IR scholars to whom we refer and to be aware of the differences among them.
Fourth, while it is useful to draw on history for IR, history also has some limits
and can be misused. In some cases, political scientists may find it hard to draw
on focused historical studies that may not be intended to connect with key
debates or theoretical notions in IR. When they do draw on history, IR scholars
and decision makers may draw the wrong lessons or inferences, while policymakers may manipulate history for partisan or policy objectives.
We can ask how history can contribute to IR, but that begs a broader
question: how can we integrate notions and insights from various disciplines in
international studies, including but beyond history and IR? Exploring the
connections between history and IR naturally leads us to this larger question,
because that exploration takes us across other disciplinary boundaries as well, a
not uncommon journey in modern world affairs, as McDermott Wernimont, and
Koopman (2011) demonstrate effectively with regard to psychology. This essay
advances what it calls an ‘‘integrated approach,’’ which can help enhance
interdisciplinarity.
Working Definitions
Since this essay is tasked in part with exploring how history can contribute to IR,
it would be useful to define both history and IR for present purposes. Much
discussion exists among historians about how to define history and the discipline
is marked by a diversity of analyses and schools of thought. In this essay, I use
the word ‘‘history’’ to refer to the work of historians and to non-historians conducting work on history. For purposes of this essay, I will adopt a definition of
history gleaned from the work of several historians. Ernst Breisach has asserted
that historians aim to demonstrate ‘‘the existence of a necessary link between
history, as reflection on the past, and human life’’ (Breisach 2007:2); the task of
historians then is to ‘‘design the great reconciliations between past, present, and
future, always cognizant of both change and continuity’’ (Breisach 2007:3). Put
another way, we can say that historians are trained to interpret past realities and
to seek ‘‘significance, explanation, and meaning’’ (Appleby, Hunt, and Jacob
1994:275) in a field that sometimes aims to understand the causes and effects of
96
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
events. As Robert Berkhofer suggests, historians wrestle with a key question of
how and what we can know of the past given that ‘‘so much of it is gone by
definition and experience’’ (Berkhofer 2008:2), and they aim to understand
history even if they know that ‘‘no two accounts of the past are the same’’ (See
Anderson, Hey, Allen Peterson, Toops, and Stevens 2008:3). As E. H. Carr
famously noted, history is much more than digging up facts—facts that in and
of themselves raise the question of what is a historical fact (Carr 1964:7; also see
Appleby et al. 1994:241–270).
Later in this essay, I will touch on different branches within the study of history.
This will provide a better sense of the diversity of thought within the discipline.
Since I will be trying to discuss what history can offer IR in the first part of this
essay, it is important to define IR as well. IR also defies easy definition and categorization. Postmodernists, for instance, might well define IR differently than realist
theorists who focus on the recurrent phenomena in world politics and embrace
the scientific method; and scholars of decision making who draw on psychology,
sociology, and other disciplines would favor a more expansive definition of IR.
Nonetheless, for the present purposes, I borrow a definition of IR as the study of
both power and conflict at the international level; power is critical because it
shapes who ‘‘wins or loses’’ in political issues, while conflict generates disputes in
the first place (Anderson et al. 2008:12–13). In this definition, IR is chiefly about
international politics at the intersection of power and conflict, and the variables
that shape power and conflict.
IR should be distinguished from IS. If IR and history are not easily circumscribed, that problem is magnified with regard to IS. As Meredith Reid Sarkees
and Marie T. Henehan point out, political science has deep roots in the United
States, but IS remains relatively young, emerging within the United States only
after World War II, and it is still evolving with competing views of its key goals
and how it should be defined (Sarkees and Henehan 2010). Debate exists on
whether to define IS as a discipline or as a multidisciplinary field (Harvey and
Brecher 2002:2). IS can be defined as an interdisciplinary field that is influenced
by a variety of disciplines; that draws on diverse methodologies, frameworks of
analysis, and theories from multiple disciplines in the effort to explain chiefly
international phenomena; and that offers an ‘‘integrative, comprehensive, and
interdisciplinary approach to issues of global importance’’ (Anderson et al.
2008:2; also, see Denemark 2010). Herein, interdisciplinary work refers to that
which draws on multiple disciplines to understand and explain phenomena.
This can be done in many ways. Thus, for example, a book on the subject of
terrorism could offer different chapters on terrorism written by historians,
psychologists, and economists.2 Or concepts from different disciplines can
be applied and ⁄ or be cross-fertilized in order to create new hybrid ideas, hypotheses, theories, and approaches.3
The Study of History and IR
Prior to exploring how history can contribute to IR, it is useful to understand
how these two disciplines differ. Varying interpretations exist about how the
2
Such an approach is presented in a prominent book on interdisciplinary studies (see Anderson et al.
2008)—also on how various disciplines approach the interdisciplinary issue of international migration, see Bommes
and Morawska (2005).
3
On different kinds of interdisciplinary research and how they can enhance peace and security studies, see
Lebow (1988). On the nature of and manner by which international law and IR theory can be cross-fertilized in an
interdisciplinary manner, see Slaughter, Tulumello, and Wood (1998). Also, for one manifestation of interdisciplinarity, see Klabbers (2009). On the history of interdisciplinarity in general and in specific disciplines, and in
particular on its manifestation in cultural studies, see Thompson (2005).
Steve Yetiv
97
study of history and IR differ, both in the field of history and IR. Some scholars
argue that an ignorance of historiographical controversies presents a much more
serious challenge to IR scholars who venture into history than the lack of
engagement of the latter with IR controversies (Lustick 1996; Little 1999;
MacDonald 2009). Whatever the case, we should take care, as historian Paul
Schroeder suggests, not to distort and exaggerate the differences between political scientists and historians (Schroeder 1997:65–67; also Schroeder 2004). Yet, it
is fair to discern several rough differences that should be viewed as falling on a
continuum rather than representing stark polar opposites.
Historians are more likely to focus on and elaborate upon single events or
more limited time periods than are IR scholars. Of course, there are many
IR scholars, as well as historians of different stripes such as Taylor (1954),
Hobsbawm (1962), Kennedy (1987), Gaddis (1982), Ferguson (2003), and
Herring (2008), who do not fit this description at all. But it is fair to describe
this as a tendency. Moreover, historians will be more satisfied with providing a
good history of a historical period, while IR scholars will not often be satisfied
with providing a historical account in and of itself.
IR scholars also often seek generalizations, while many historians are more
likely to see events as sui generis, even though neither historians nor political
scientists can really avoid simplification given the great complexity of what they
study. Generalization and specification are different undertakings, but they are
neither necessarily dichotomous nor separate on the path toward discovery. It
may be true, as Isaiah Berlin suggests in his study of Tolstoy, that some thinkers
are like ‘‘foxes’’ in that they seek to explain and see events through multiple
lenses, while others are like ‘‘hedgehogs’’ who see the world through the focus
upon a central idea (Berlin 1953). But overall, we need both types of thinkers
for knowledge to be advanced over a long period of time.
If IR scholars are more likely to seek generalizations, they are also more likely
to see events in terms of existing generalizations. In one symposium chiefly
involving diplomatic historians and IR scholars, contributors tended to find that
‘‘unlike international historians, who did not expect explanations for a particular historical episode to be consistent with arguments for other events, political
scientists assumed that particular historical outcomes and processes could be
treated as examples of a larger phenomenon’’ (Elman and Elman 2008:358).4
While some historians, as historian Stephen Pelz observes, do use generalizations
and theories to explain events, ‘‘even if they are reluctant to admit to the
practice’’ (Pelz in Elman 2008:87), IR scholars are far more conscious of theory
and see it as an endpoint. One might say that historians reveal pieces of a puzzle. They know that they have limited meaning in themselves, but they believe
that others will use them to construct the larger picture in longer-range,
broader, or comparative studies. Political science, on the other hand, prioritizes
the essential in an attempt at parsimony which is often believed to be where one
will end one’s investigation. For IR scholars, generalization is used for prediction, whereas historians generalize to streamline history so that it can be
explained. Otherwise, they could write a million volumes on any period of
history.
IR scholars are also more likely to interpret great powers as pursuing grand
strategies. As with the aforementioned symposium, several contributors involved
in a 2008 symposium agreed that ‘‘much of mainstream IR is fixed on the
notion that international relations are repetitive, timeless, and cyclical’’ (Elman
and Elman 2008:359). A particular branch of foreign policy studies claims that
states pursue coherent, consistent strategies over extended periods of time—that
4
On this symposium, see Elman and Elman (2001).
98
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
their behavior conforms with a grand strategy such as balance of power or hegemonic grand strategy (see, for example, Art 2003). By contrast, historians are
less likely to see world affairs in terms of a grand narrative (see Reus-Smit
2008:400–402).
Another difference is that IR scholars sometimes seek to make predictions,
while historians are loathe to do so. This does not diminish the value of their
work for IR scholars, but it creates a separate, disconnected space of inquiry and
analysis. The same can be said of policy. Many IR scholars seek to make policy
recommendations, while this would be far more rare among historians, with
some notable exceptions (for instance, Neustadt and May 1986).
Whatever the exact differences between the disciplines, some scholars see an
increasing convergence between them. They identify a so-called historical turn
in IR in which history is being brought back increasingly into IR analysis; in
which qualitative research is gaining ground, thus putting some IR scholars in a
better position to draw on the work of historians (see Elman and Elman
2008:361–64). For his part, Keene goes so far as to argue that the ‘‘new history’’
has moved beyond chronological description and narrative into greater analysis
that resembles political science (Keene 2008:381–389).
But What History and What IR?
Such a historical turn may be in the making for what history can offer IR, but I
argue that understanding what history can offer IR depends on asking to which
historians and political scientists do we refer? Different schools in both disciplines bring varying ontologies to bear in their work; different core assumptions
about the nature of interaction in the human condition and world politics; and
about the critical actors, processes, and interactions that produce outcomes.
Thus, for neorealists, anarchy socializes states, and variations in state capabilities
are central. In contrast, constructivists privilege ideas and socially constructed
norms in shaping outcomes over material structures and capabilities. These
ontological differences fundamentally affect which IR scholars can learn best
from which historians.
At the most basic level, I argue that qualitative IR scholars can benefit more
from the work of historians than can quantitative IR scholars, although both can
certainly benefit. Qualitative scholars can benefit more because the quantitative
scholars are more likely to embrace abstraction and to detach from historical
analyses. Game theorists can certainly benefit from a better understanding of
the context that they model, as can agent-based modelers and other types of
simulation modelers. Such knowledge can generate more useful assumptions
about how actors and systems behave and can also help calibrate models.
However, they can also model without great knowledge of any event or context.
In fact, some modelers would argue strongly in the area of game theory, or for
instance, simulation modeling, that abstraction is a much better approach
toward analysis—even a sine qua non for efficacy.
Partly due to this view of the role of empirics, and partly because assumptions
need not be realistic to be useful if they help illuminate realities, it is fair to
argue that game theorists can benefit less from historians than can, for instance,
neoclassical realists whose approaches invite and require good historical analysis.
By this, I mean that the central thrust of neoclassical realism is that balance of
power dynamics cannot in and of themselves explain key outcomes such as
balancing and bandwagoning; rather, it is also vital to incorporate micro-level
variables such as perception, ideology, and domestic-society relations to explain
these outcomes. In turn, it is difficult to understand micro-level variables, which
are not as easily amenable to abstraction as are balance of power dynamics,
with slender historical analysis. In fact, the main methodological approach of
Steve Yetiv
99
neoclassical realists is to test hypotheses and theories using the process-tracing
of case studies (see Christensen 1997; Rose 1998; Schweller 2003).
Within both fields, there are more particular genres to consider for a sensible
rendering of what history can offer IR. Hobson and Lawson identify several
schools of thought among historians, which, while hardly exhaustive, underscore
the diversity of thought in the discipline.
The school of Radical Historicism, insofar as it can be discerned, assumes that
good history must consider the realities of a given time and place, which shape
events; postcolonial studies provide an example of such an approach, which
brings it closer to constructivist IR, albeit bereft of the grand scope analysis of
Wendt (1999). By contrast, traditional historians aim to capture truth through
archival work ⁄ primary documents. Such approaches are averse to the work of
Radical Historicism (Hobson and Lawson 2008:426). While traditional historians
produce work that differs from that of IR theorists, IR positivists may well see
the work of traditional historians as most useful out of the different approaches
in history. They can draw upon it to test their theories in a positivist manner.
Meanwhile, in contrast to scholars from the other two schools, historical sociologists are not focused on a ‘‘random series of isolated movements,’’ but rather
on the broader sweep of events, employing more generality.5 Big picture historians seek to examine large-scale change, but that is also the central province of
historical sociologists who have interacted profitably with some branches of history and IR (Lawson 2006: especially 408–409). As Lawson (2007:344) describes
it, historical sociology, which can be viewed as at least two centuries old, involves
efforts by economists, philosophers, and sociologists to reveal, through the study
of history, a generally applicable analysis of how core features of the modern
world evolved, including capitalism, democracy, and industrialization. Thus, the
study of history is combined with sociology’s effort to reveal why historical work
is significant in terms of the social world. Because of its scope and goals, Hobson
and Lawson suggest that a historical sociological approach offers a better chance
of dialogue with IR theorists than the traditional historical approach (Hobson
and Lawson 2008). And these historians are well suited to the task of advancing
the study of change in IR, due to their scope of study and orientation.
I would argue that, in contrast, IR constructivists are far less likely to learn
from traditional historians than from social or cultural historians. Reus-Smit, for
instance, sees constructivist IR as more compatible with social and cultural history, because the latter tend to reject the notion that historical work can reveal
one truth as opposed to multiple truths. Likewise, in a similar vein, postmodern
historians largely reject the notion of objective histories and instead see history
as a function of how we perceive it, making it important to consider events from
different perspectives. Such an approach makes their work more valuable to
postmodern IR scholars than to positivists. In this case, it is not just a question
of ontological congruence but also of epistemology; about the central question
of what we can know and of how we know what we think we know. If two scholars differ on these central questions, they will likely find it harder to benefit
from each other’s work.
Meanwhile, on the perennial question of theory, some scholars draw a distinction among schools of history. Historian John Lynn, for example, distinguishes
between traditional and so called ‘‘avant-garde’’ historians. The latter embrace
theory, even with ‘‘passion,’’ albeit such theory ‘‘is not the type that international relations specialists would feel comfortable with…;’’ that being theory
imported mainly from ‘‘philosophy, literary criticism, and anthropology’’ (Lynn
5
On the nature of this school and on the three waves of historical sociology, see Hobson and Lawson
(2008:427–435).
100
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
2001:360–361). One obvious exception is the increasingly prominent alternative
schools, anchored by postmodernism and parts of the constructivist literature.
To be sure, much overlap exists within the divisions discussed above. Thus,
cultural ⁄ constructivist approaches are also normally archivally based. And
‘‘traditional history’’ involving detailed archival work can be complimentary to
the broad qualitative, sociological, constructivist, postmodern categories sometimes typologized under ‘‘Radical Historicism.’’ Even so, the question of what
historians and what IR scholars we are discussing remains salient. Methodological, theoretical, and empirical differences certainly exist in both fields.
Exploring Change: History and IR
This essay advances the notion that history can offer IR much in the study of
change. To be sure, IR scholars have explored change in important ways (such
as Biersteker and Weber 1996; Blyth 2002; Clark 2007; Crawford 2002; Gilpin
1981; Goldstein 1988; Holsti 2004; Hui 2005; Ikenberry 2001; Kugler and
Organski 1989; Legro 2007; MacDonald 2009; Modelski and Thompson 1996;
Nexon 2009; and Philpott 2001). However, the work of IR scholars could be
enhanced with a better understanding of short- and longer-run change.
Exploring Short-Run Change: The Comparative Method
Historical study can be of great value to IR in diachronic comparisons aimed at
revealing causality, and, in turn, changes over a relatively shorter period of time.
A sophisticated literature exists regarding debates about the implications of temporality for social-scientific inquiry (see, for example, Abbott 2001; Bartleson
1995; Bearman, Moody, and Faris 2002; Crouch and Farrell 2004; Mahoney and
Rueschmeyer 2003; and Tilly 1995). The debates touch on critical areas including how to view historical processes themselves—a question that could define
what the analyst considers to be germane in the first place (see Abbott 2001:
especially chapter 5). Space prevents exploring these works in further detail, but
it is fair to say that some of the most salient contributions in IR and other disciplines hinge on discovering, or theorizing about, correlations between or among
variables or, at a higher level, cause-effect links. It seems, then, that we should
be interested in understanding what best enables this enterprise. There are
many paths to discovery and understanding, but the study of history and IR,
separately and together, is important to this enterprise in central ways.
Historical study can be of use to IR in diachronic comparisons by helping illuminate what has changed out of a broader context of interacting and evolving
variables. Originally associated with John Stuart Mill, the diachronic comparative
method of difference can advance the study of IR across a range of critical issue
areas and is seriously under-utilized by students and scholars.
The comparative method is used to compare cases that in theory differ in only
one significant respect. This would approximate an experiment in which one
group receives a stimulus while another does not. Any changes in the experimental group might then be attributed to the stimulus. Nothing in world politics
really resembles such a controlled experiment. However, the diachronic
approach addresses the problem of controlling variables better than do crossnational studies because it involves more constants and fewer variables (Lijphart
1971:689). That is, fewer variables change over just time than over both time
and area.
While in statistics one variable can be held constant while others fluctuate,
that is not possible with history. One cannot change history to eliminate and
then to recreate an event or action, be it a peace treaty, trade agreement, or
change of regime, thus controlling for it and revealing correlation.
Steve Yetiv
101
Consequently, it is necessary to improvise methodologically. Such an effort
involves many considerations, but at the core, it is vital to grapple with two basic
threats to valid inference. The first refers to specific events other than the action
under study that might account for observed effects. The second threat is called
maturation. It refers to regular changes correlated with the passage of time and
is distinguished from history in that it refers to processes rather than to discrete
events (Campbell 1988:226–227).
Addressing threats to valid inference helps separate the effects of the action in
question from those of other variables. A before ⁄ after comparison of the effects
of such actions helps assess these effects. Historical study, be it by historians or
others, can be vital to such before ⁄ after comparisons. This is because it adds context and depth to the analysis which can help address threats to valid inference.
This is true even if the before ⁄ after comparison is based on data analysis. That
can be supplemented by examining the context in which it has meaning.
Work by historians on how minor events can alter history may be of particular
use to IR scholars that seek before ⁄ after diachronic comparisons. This is because
the minor event is circumscribed enough to lend itself to such analysis. Historian A.J.P. Taylor, for instance, is famous for showing how minor events can have
major unintended consequences (1954, 1965).
Long-Run Change and IR Theory
History not only aids in understanding short-term change, but also in grasping
long-term dynamics. History is vital for judging change in the first place. As
Ferguson and Mansbach put it (2009:366), ‘‘To know if and how change has
taken place, it is necessary to have a baseline—the past—against which to compare and contrast the present.’’ As scholars, we sometimes make claims or
assumptions about how much things have changed or not changed over time.
Take the related but different issues of American empire and decline. Some
thinkers assert that the United States is an empire like those of the past (O’Reilly
2008), while others contest this point in part by arguing that it is not an empire
because, unlike great powers of the past, it does not aggrandize territory
(Nye 1990). These types of works are very interesting and important and could be
further developed or explored with comparative historical work that analyzes the
great empires of the past, such as that of Burbank and Cooper which argues, in
surveying key empires in history, that their decline was triggered in large part by
virtue of the challenges they faced in controlling their outer boundaries (2010).
Historians have engaged these questions of empire for some time. The literature by historians is full of such work, dating back to Thucydides, but in more
modern times to Gibbon and his Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire through the
seminal and acclaimed work of Fernand Braudel (1972), who investigated the
clash of empires and cultures in the Mediterranean in the sixteenth century by
looking broadly at contexts (agricultural, financial, economic, demographic,
technological, etc.) and back through historical development over a millennium.
In more recent times, historians of various stripes have addressed questions of
empire (for example, Kennedy 1987; Maier 2006; Porter 2006). As MacDonald
(2009) points out, the historiography of British and American political expansion can inform contemporary debates on empire and change in important ways.
For instance, some argue that historiography reveals the limitations of commonly
cited arguments that the United States is an empire simply because it is powerful
or that it is anti-imperial simply because it disavows conquest (MacDonald
2009:65).
Another prominent area of inquiry serves as a further example. At the empirical level, scholars have produced useful work on whether the United States is in
decline, but this analysis could be further developed with systematic comparison
102
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
across time. The question of American decline is not new. In more recent
times—the 1980s—Japan was viewed by some thinkers (for example, Kennedy
1987) as in a position to supplant American domination, while others disputed
that notion (for example, Nye 1990). However, the question of American
decline has risen anew at the turn of the twenty-first century. Even President
Barack Obama stressed in his inaugural speech that the country has a ‘‘nagging
fear that America’s decline is inevitable.’’ This was not hyperbole, given the
collapse of Wall Street icons like Bear Stearns; the credit and auto industry
crises; falling economic output; exploding national debt; seemingly endless war
in Afghanistan and Iraq; global image problems; and the rise of potential
contenders, namely China.
The question of the extent to which, if any, the United States is in serious
decline begs a method. It can be judged with a systematic comparison to previous periods and to other actors. Preferably, it would involve comparing US capability over time and its power relative to that of other actors. To do so, we could
start by operationalizing American capability in basic ways (GDP; percentage of
companies in the Fortune 500; B.A., M.A., and Ph.D. degrees; percentage of global regimes that are democratic, etc.). We then could develop more sophisticated measures from them and compare these indicators across time.
However, such analysis also could benefit from more in-depth history, not just
in the sense that the indicators would be compared across successive historical
periods, but also in that history could offer context within which to better
enable the interpretation of our data and possibly point to indicators that
deserve to be included in the first place. As Gaddis argues, historians ‘‘know that
every concept is embedded in a context, and that the only things permanent
about contexts is that they shift’’ (Gaddis 2001:321). But it is not just this propensity that can inform the study of change, but also the work itself or of others
conducting historical work. Thus, it might be sensible to examine America’s role
in international economic institutions or to examine a central issue area over
time in order to see whether Washington achieved its goals in that issue area,
more or less over time. It might be that it had capability on paper,6 but that for
reasons that historical analysis might inform, its capability was not very fungible
or translatable into influence. It might be useful to examine its position and disposition relative to that of other great powers that declined in order to assess
whether the US has unique characteristics that can allow it to escape what befell
them.
Perhaps we would discover that America’s management or domination of technological change had diminished or increased over time, making it all the more
critical to understand the link between technology and world politics. Anticipating the contribution of Fritsch (2001), this is a natural point at which to note
the absence of technology studies from the dialogue. Revolution and even evolution in technology presents a challenge to causal inference across the board,
because increasingly observed effects in world politics can be traced back to the
technological revolution. As Fritsch underscores, the global diffusion of technology has accelerated across all areas of human endeavour. This has generated
serious consequences for global prosperity and for human welfare—consequences that have been understudied empirically and neglected in the study of
IR and in IS more broadly.
Social scientists sometimes make claims about long-range change, but infrequently they focus on the near-term. As Pierson (2003) puts it, in looking for
contiguous causes and outcomes, they can sometimes miss important factors.
This is because some processes take a very long time to unfold and often fall
6
The vaunted Correlates of War project would be useful in this respect.
Steve Yetiv
103
outside the scope of social science analysis. Certainly, that would be true of our
examples here of American empire and potential decline, not to mention that
of other great powers in history.
Second, at the theoretical level, the question of change in world politics is critical, because the main theories of IR make fundamental assumptions about
change. Assessing the extent to which these claims or assumptions are on target
or are useful requires some understanding of history. Of course, some IR scholars may feel no need to be bothered with history inasmuch as assumptions do
not have to be realistic to be useful. After all, the rationality assumption is crucial to economics and to various fields of political science. Yet, while assumptions can be useful even when they are unrealistic—successful predictive models
often fit that description—there can be value in assessing to what extent they
conform with reality. This message is reinforced by the exegesis of neuroscience
and decision making from Zak and Kugler (2011).
Realists ⁄ neorealists assume that world politics is cyclical; that wars recur; that
cooperation is perpetually difficult to achieve; that not much changes at the
heart of world politics (Waltz 1979; Mearsheimer 2001). By contrast, their detractors in the liberal ⁄ neoliberal school, as well as constructivists such as Wendt
(1999), assume fundamentally that much changes over time, be it the rise and
impact of international institutions (Keohane 1984, 1987; Keohane and Martin
1995:39–51; Martin and Simmons 1998:729–757; Russett and Oneal 2001; Dai
2007); evolutionary learning across history; changes in global culture from
Hobbesian to Lockean to Kantian (Wendt 1999), or of the development and
effects of globalization (for instance, Rosenau 1997; Russett and Oneal 2001; Keohane and Nye 2001; Held and McGrew 2002).
All of these claims, be they theoretical or empirical, beg questions about history and change. For example, one major difference between IR theoretical
schools has to do with globalization. Some scholars believe that it has generated
a radically different global environment, in sharp contrast to the assumptions of
realism. Thus, some theoretical attention focuses on the notion that under globalized conditions, small perturbations might ‘‘reverberate’’ or cause ‘‘cascading
disruptions’’—dynamics that researchers have noticed in other forms of globalization (Jervis 1997; Rosenau 2003: chapter 9; Maoz 2006). As Rosenau suggests,
there is now a ‘‘widespread understanding that unexpected events are commonplace, that anomalies are normal occurrences, that minor incidents can mushroom into major outcomes... ’’ (Rosenau 2003:209).
IR has something to learn from history here, whether or not the historical
work consulted by IR scholars was intended to illuminate the question of how
much has really changed in terms of globalization. Analyses of different periods
of history could be consulted by IR scholars to offer information useful for
comparing different periods and could engender more fruitful exchange among
historians and political scientists, not to mention the fodder for induction about
the conditions under which change is most likely to occur. For instance, some
scholars would argue that the world was more globalized in the nineteenth
century than it would be 100 years later. The nineteenth century is sometimes
called ‘‘The First Era of Globalization,’’ because it was characterized by high
international trade and investment between the European imperial powers, their
colonies, and, later, the United States. Whatever one thinks of it, it is commonly
believed that this period of globalization began to break down with World War I
and then the Great Depression in the early 1930s. By looking back at previous
periods, it is easier to evaluate to what extent globalization in the economic, cultural, and technological sphere has risen on the back of institutional efforts to
decrease trade barriers and costs. These institutions, founded at Breton Woods,
New Hampshire after World War II, include the World Bank; the International
Monetary Fund; and the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (now World
104
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
Trade Organization), which launched a number of subsequent agreements to
remove restrictions on trade.
Greater historical comparison may well reveal that while economic interaction
was high in the nineteenth century, it was different in many ways from economic
interaction today, making the contemporary arena more interdependent. In
addition to economic globalization, more historical comparisons would be of
value regarding technological, political, and cultural globalization. It is hard to
question the rise of numerous technologies linked to the internet and wireless
interaction, and their massive impact on economic, political, and cultural relations, but just how different are such technologies and their effects on various
areas of world politics? Political globalization has expanded as well, as reflected
in the massive rise in the number of global organizations, international treaties,
and agreements, but to what extent have they shaped international interaction
across a range of areas, including business, space, conflict, energy, and the
oceans? Cultural globalization can be viewed as the rise of cultural exchanges
and practices among nations and peoples. But just how different is this dimension today compared to one or two centuries ago?
Furthermore, understanding change, partly via the use of historical work, can
help in theory-building. As Ferguson and Mansbach suggest, ‘‘IR theorists who
lack historical sensitivity simply assume that the past resembles the present’’
(Ferguson and Mansbach 2008:378). And that can bedevil the ability to generate
theory, especially in terms of theories about change in world politics, of which
there is a relative dearth. Hegemonic war theory, power cycle theory, power transition theory, and long-cycle war theory, for instance, are theories of change, as
is Wendt’s social theory of international politics (1999), but there are not many
of this kind. Neorealism, according to Waltz and his critics, cannot explain
change (Waltz 1979:323–330), although some scholars disagree with Waltz’s view
of his own theory (Hobson and Lawson 2008:418–419). Others might say that
neorealism is a theory of change insofar as it indirectly explains why things do
not change; why certain patterns of behavior—balances—recur in world politics,
under the unrelenting, seemingly immutable nature of anarchy. But non-change
is a different dependent variable than change. Explaining persistence and
change are not the same undertakings, albeit Waltzian theory provides one perspective on prospects for core change in world politics.
Revealing Causal Connections and Path Dependency
History can help not only in understanding change over time, but also in the
related effort of understanding how events are connected or of recognizing the
importance of path dependency. This is the notion that a causal dependence
exists between prior events and processes and contemporary events and processes.
Single, detailed case studies, or a combination of many studies or books culled
from the literature, facilitate efforts to see how one event leads to another. That
makes it easier to ascribe causality in history’s train. This would be harder to
accomplish from more streamlined analyses of the past which lack the deep context for revealing how seemingly unrelated events might well be connected.
Without historical understanding, it is harder to explain why the United States
invaded Iraq in 2003, an act that was shaped over a period of two decades or
more. That such connections are in play is not the story, but little political science work actually tries to tease them out of the historical process, in contrast to
the work of, for instance, historical institutionalism that is more attuned to such
longer-run analysis (See Thelen 1999, 2005).
In fact, it is not uncommon in IR to offer explanations that lack historical
background, despite the large literature of historically informed social science
on the causes of war. Such work can facilitate efforts to identify the cause-effect
Steve Yetiv
105
connections that can inform broader generalizations about issues such as the
causes of war. It can also inform broader questions: do major powers tend to
pursue grand strategies over time such as hegemonic strategy (Layne 2006) or
do they tend to be reactive to events over which they lack control? Why do countries use force in lieu of pursuing a bargaining outcome? Do wars cause future
wars? Does an imbalance of power cause war?
IR scholars sometimes ask even larger questions that deal with change, which
may or may not be spurred by an understanding of history but which can be
addressed in part by understanding history: for instance—why have empires
declined? Answering such questions can benefit from history because they
assume a comparison to past events and variables.
We might also ask theory-oriented questions that require some understanding
of how history is connected across much longer periods of time: for instance,
how did events in one century shape another? Does the concentration of power
lead to war (e.g., did German unification in 1870 contribute to the eventual outbreak of World War I?) as neorealists might ‘‘postdict’’; or does concentrated
power plus the behavior of leaders (Wilhelm II, assuming power in Germany in
1890) illuminate the causes of war (World War I), as neoclassical theorists might
posit? Or are these simplifications privileging parsimony at the expense of fidelity? Mainstream IR theorists abstract away from the individual level and assume
in part that state preferences are either invariable or not shaped by individual
beliefs. However, a greater understanding of the role of individuals in history
might indicate where it might be profitable to combine levels of analysis, while
retaining parsimony, and can surely benefit foreign policy theory.
Of course, historians are not the only ones who study history in a way that can
help IR thinkers understand change. Beyond the historical work of some IR
scholars such as the neoclassical realists, three large schools of thought deserve
mention here, if only in brief. The first school, historical sociology, has already
been touched upon. The second school is comparative historical analysis, which
is composed mainly of sociologists or IR scholars. Comparative historical analysts
are concerned with causal analysis in processes over time, such as the causes of
social revolutions or the formation of states; they seek to assess causality via
studying similar and contrasting cases and statistical large-N analyses. However,
the bifurcation between these thinkers is not clear, and they often build upon
each other’s work. Thus, as Amenta (2003:97) points out, according to ‘‘some
standard views, comparative and historical research involves a division of labor
in which historians work for social scientists.’’ In fact, many historians pursue
larger goals than that.
Historical institutionalism constitutes the third school. It is largely concerned
with revealing why, at a macro-level that can span centuries, countries evolved
along different developmental paths; and how state institutions emerged from
enduring legacies of political struggles. Such work is important to contemporary
comparativists in political science as well as to IR scholars who are interested in
the links between subnational and international phenomena. This is in part
because, as Thelen suggests, ‘‘knowing how institutions were constructed provides
insights into how they might come apart’’ (1999; 400). Historical institutionalism
is different from but can also inform rational choice institutionalism which seeks
to understand the coordinating functions of institutions (see Thelen 1999).
Theory-Building, Modeling, and Testing
The study of history and of change may provide inputs into IR theory-building
and testing. As political scientists Gary King, Robert Keohane, and Sidney Verba
effectively demonstrate (1994: 42–43), detailed studies can offer some basis for
106
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
inference to broader generalization and aid in the most difficult task that social
science faces—simplification.
For his part, Gaddis points out that process tracing, which involves making
deductions about how events and processes are connected with references to
general principles across disciplines, is not much different from what historians
do (in Gaddis 2001:324). Whether done by historians, political scientists, or others, process tracing, in aiming to uncover causal links, can then serve as fodder
for building, testing, and refining hypotheses and theory. Indeed, process seeks
to identify through a theory-informed approach a causal chain that links independent and dependent variables (see Bennett and George 2005:206–207),
which represents a central case study method (see Bennett and Elman 2007).
In this sense, and in others, qualitative and quantitative work are similar and
can inform each other (King, Keohane, and Verba 1994; Box-Steffensmeier,
Brady, and Collier 2008). General theory-building or modeling, be it in the form
of statistics, game theory, or various forms of simulation, requires a sense of how
things hang together in reality; of how variables are related. The parsimony that
even purist IR theorists seek need not preclude the value of historical study.
Rather, such study can augment the search for what the critical variables should
be in the first place and how they might be correlated or causally connected.
Presumably, at least some of the most abstract thoughts in IR must have their
genesis in something observed. IR phenomena are not like physics or mathematics where imagination is a sufficient leap for theory-building and for eventual
discovery. Einstein did not observe the phenomena about which he theorized,
but the leading lights of IR theory certainly observed the modern subjects of
world politics and presumably have some education in history.
Some might argue that a better understanding of the Great Depression might
have led risk modelers on Wall Street to include variables in their models helpful to predicting or even limiting the Wall Street meltdown of 2008. The other
contributions to the symposium offer similar observations about how political
processes may be more fully understood, anticipated, and even altered (at least
implicitly) through greater understanding of psychological, technological, and
neuroactive forces.
Historical evidence, of course, may be used in quantitative approaches, even if
not conducted by historians. Thus, some comparative historical analysis uses
large-N statistical analysis, such as the analysis of revolutions. While the level of
detail in this work which is conducted often by sociologists falls short of that of
traditional historians, it is more involved than that of most political scientists,
but it feeds into the study of IR (see Goldstone 2003).
Historical evidence can also be critical for testing hypotheses and theories,
especially in areas where metadata or artificial evidence are prominent, and
quantitative methods are neither possible nor appropriate for the subject matter.
As Larson points out, historical evidence is ‘‘essential to assess the accuracy of
psychological explanations of foreign policy decisions,’’ because experiments
generate useful hypotheses about cognitive and motivational influence, albeit in
an artificial environment, in need of ‘‘validation by real-world data’’ (Larson
2001:327).
Of course, history also can be a laboratory for the study of counterfactuals, as
a means for drawing inference or testing theory. Such ‘‘what if’’ questions,
which are employed across disciplines, can help identify the importance of
hypothesized variables that are assumed to have been absent. Often, such variables may be tied to broader theories, allowing for those theories to be tested, if
the counterfactual approach is used effectively. Indeed, all counterfactuals are
not created equal. As is well known, they can be misused, especially if the variable assumed to have been absent is too divorced in time from the outcome that
it is hypothesized to explain (Tetlock and Belkin 1996; King and Zeng 2007).
Steve Yetiv
107
History may also help, to some extent, in calibrating models. For instance,
assume that one develops an agent-based simulation model to study the impact
of terrorist attacks on the global shipping system. One can populate the model
with actors whose behavior is governed by algorithms that approximate how
those actors are likely to behave, but calibrating the model requires identifying
past events that may approximate terrorist attacks, such as earthquakes or labor
strikes and then assessing their effects. Since we cannot create terrorist attacks,
these other events help assess whether our model captures the essential effects
that it purports to predict and explain. Historians may offer the work that, when
combined with data analysis of such effects, can help in identifying cases and
their key contours for calibrating models of various stripes, or non-historians can
engage in historical analysis for this purpose.7
Historians who are especially interested in theory—some of it even IR theory—should also cooperate more with theory-oriented IR scholars. We see little
published work of this kind. Yet, historians, as Gaddis points out, must strike a
balance between particularization and generalization (see Gaddis 2002, especially pp. 14–15), as must many IR scholars, and so there is an area of intersection that can be exploited better.
The technical methods of IR and sociology may also help in understanding
history, producing a two-way street of interaction. For instance, modelers have
tried to represent critical nodes in history in models in order to understand the
historical process better. Exploiting social network analysis, scholars have
attempted to answer questions of this kind: when, if ever, do single events
change history (Bearman et al. 2002)? This question is of obvious cross-disciplinary significance, and answering it would enrich an understanding of history and
also of the conditions under which events produce major effects—in other
words, it would provide key information for theory-building.
History and Non-Positivist Agendas
Beyond the positivist agenda, IR scholars of a different type can benefit from history. For instance, some IR constructivists can use history in their own way. They
can draw upon the work of social and cultural historians in particular. This is
because they share certain ontological claims, allowing for greater inter-operability of thought and analysis. The historical work of social and cultural historians
tends to be shaped in ways that they can tap. If they seek to understand the perspective of many Palestinians and Israelis about any event in their struggle
(Israel’s independence in 1948, for example, or the 1967 Six Day War), such
historians are more likely to provide such accounts.
Scholars identify a so-called cultural turn in the social sciences, and certainly
cultural studies and postmodernism have gained some ground in IR. These
schools of thought consist of numerous approaches that defy easy categorization
and can overlap with constructivism, but they tend to reject causal analysis as a
central goal of social sciences and instead highlight the implications of context
for inter-subjective understandings over perceived causal relations within them
(Mahoney and Rueschmeyer 2003: especially 21–23).
In contrast to social and cultural historians who may be more able to interface
with IR constructivists and postmodernists, traditional historians will seek to
discover what actually occurred in historical events, with far less regard or even
disdain for multiple perspectives or contingent truths. However, that is not to say
that the work of traditional historians cannot benefit IR constructivists and
postmodernists. They can draw on such historical accounts to try to understand
7
On approaches to, and challenges regarding, scientific progress in IS, see James (2002).
108
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
better the influences of ideas. This may help them assemble disparate historical
accounts of how culture and ideas have shaped lenses of actors, and in turn political action, and how those lenses interacted with the environments in which they
sought to generate outcomes (for a brief example, see Reus-Smit 2008:411–414).
The Limits of History for IR Scholars
A number of limits and misuses of history are worth mentioning in brief. History
can only take us so far in the study of IR, partly because pure deduction is sometimes its own intellectual leap, anchored in the mind’s ether with only modest
empirical moorings. Pure IR theorists could study one hundred historical cases
and still not ferret out insightful generalizations for theory. Imagination, even if
uninformed, can be its own engine of discovery.
Some IR scholars such as those who want to use history to test theory may
question the extent to which historians have achieved an ‘‘accurate’’ narrative,
because most IR scholars will lack the knowledge of the event or period in question to make a good judgment. While historians can help IR scholars in understanding change, that presupposes that we understand history well enough to
use it as a benchmark and that we also have a clear grasp of the present to compare with the past. As political scientist Ian Lustick points out, we cannot treat
the work of historians as an ‘‘unproblematic background narrative from which
theoretical neutral data can be elicited for the framing of problems and the testing of theories’’ (1996:604).
Insofar as those engaged in historical study are unaware of IR theory, they are
not concerned with, or possibly able to ferret out, connections in their work that
are salient for IR theory. Thus, it is up to theorists to discern such connections
in material that may not be suited for such purposes. That creates the potential
for intellectual dislocation or for seeing in history the patterns of theory not
intended by the historian.
To be sure, some historians are engaged in all sorts of generalizations, causal
analysis, and theoretically-informed work; they are not simply atheoretical
recorders of processes and events whose work IR scholars must trust for their
own purposes. However, in some cases, political scientists can have difficulty
drawing on extremely focused historical studies that do not connect with key
questions, debates, or theoretical notions in IR. The extent of the problem will
depend on many factors, including the subject matter, the goals of the scholars,
the epistemological and ontological assumptions of their enterprise both within
and between the disciplines, and how their work is presented and located in the
literature. All historians, of course, are not the same. As noted earlier, some historians, such as Gaddis (1982), Kennedy (1987), and George Herring (2008),
help meet this challenge by producing works of breadth that tie into the IS literature on issues such as strategies of containment; the decline of empires; and
the nature of great power behavior and the causes of war. That makes it easier
for them to have a dialogue with political scientists.
Of course, it is true that history can serve the practical goal of informing
decision makers, on the assumption that if they knew more history, they would
be more likely to make better decisions (Neustadt and May 1986). As Joseph
Nye, who served in high-level policy-making positions in the administration of
President Bill Clinton, illuminates quite effectively, theory, history, and policy go
hand in hand and should not be regarded as separate efforts (George 1993;
Nye 2009). But history can also mislead us if, for instance, we are seduced by
historical analogies that do not fit present conditions. As they say, a cat that has
sat on a hot stove may not sit on one again, but nor will it sit on a cold stove.
Santayana’s famous warning may be true, but it may also be true that those who
remember history may not understand the present.
Steve Yetiv
109
As Kammen (2008) rightly explains, history can be misused for partisan or
policy objectives. Those who invoke it may be pushing their own agendas. Or, in
the view of a constructivist, they are constructing reality using history for political
goals. It may also be that, even if the history is accurate, its lessons may be too
complex to understand; subjected to different interpretations by different actors;
or too painful to put in effect (see Heisler 2008).
Synergies across Borders
Some historians think negatively that political scientists know little about a lot,
while some political scientists think that historians know a lot about little of
import. These views are not productive. Nor are the divisions between comparativists and IR scholars, the qualitative and quantitative thinkers, inductive and
deductive thinkers, and positivists and non-positivists. Or between the economists who see themselves as closest to the hard sciences, and their critics who
see them as unable to explain or predict much, outside the confines of optimistic rationality assumptions and artificial models.
McDermott, Wernimont, and Koopman (2011) offer a constructive way forward on the latter intellectual stalemate, in which rational choice is seen as a
basic model of human behavior in need of elaboration and even modification
by context. In short, derived from various flawed dichotomies, ‘‘all or nothing’’
views divide departments, disciplines, and scholars at least some of whom should
really be asking how their disciplines can most profitably inform each other. But
the question arises as to how it might be possible to build bridges within and
across disciplines in a systematic manner and to create synergies across different
levels of analysis. As former International Studies Association President Michael
Brecher put it a decade ago in his presidential address, failure to do so has
‘‘long bedeviled International Studies’’ (Brecher 1999:229). While progress
has been made since his address, his exhortations to cross epistemological,
empirical, and theoretical borders through sensible integration within and across
disciplines still make eminent sense, especially in a world whose problems
increasingly cross borders and intersect across disciplines.
The Integrated Approach for Enhancing Interdisciplinary Study
So far, the essay has focused on what history can offer IR, but it now seeks to
explore the second question of the essay which examines how to enhance interdisciplinarity in IS. Asking what history can contribute to IR is part of this
inquiry, but now I seek to present what I call the ‘‘integrated approach.’’ Such
approaches, I believe, may spur thought on how to enhance interdisciplinarity
in international studies.
It is sensible here to draw upon the example with which I am most familiar—my book, Explaining Foreign Policy (Yetiv 2004, 2011). It introduced what I
called the ‘‘integrated approach’’ for the study of government behavior. Drawing
on this work can illustrate the broader concept of ‘‘integrative approaches’’ that
I seek to advance here.
The integrated approach consists of using different perspectives to help
explain government behavior: how decisions are made (decision making) and
why governments do what they do, or the reasons for their actions. The goal of
the integrated approach is to explain a foreign policy behavior such as the
choice to go to war, to sign a peace treaty, or to make an alliance using different
cuts on reality derived from different models or perspectives.
After offering these competing explanations of the same behavior, we then test
these perspectives or different model-driven narratives against the record. I argue
that doing so can yield insights that can be integrated into better explanations of
110
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
government behavior than we would have in using just one perspective or model
as a guide to explanation. After testing the perspectives against the record, the
integrated approach can also be used to bridge areas of theory that tend to be
treated as separate, such as the domains of system structure and individual psychology as identified by McDermott, Wernimont, and Koopman (2011). Thus, a
rational actor model explanation could be combined at the system level with an
individual-level explanation to enhance overall explanation.
Cross-fertilization of notions and insights from different disciplines is fairly
common in foreign policy studies and elsewhere, such as between economics
and psychology (for instance, see Ariely 2008, 2010) in the increasingly important field of behavioral economics.8 Such cross-fertilization is also attempted in
various other ways between psychology and political science in areas of political
psychology (for instance, see McDermott 2004; Welch 2005; Renshon and
Suedfeld 2007) or in the more specific field of prospect theory (Levy 1997;
McDermott 2004). Efforts in political science to integrate cognitive and rational
theories in particular overlap these various fields and subfields (Mintz 2003;
Mintz and DeRouen 2010). It is very difficult to develop a broad and sophisticated understanding of rationality—one of the central concepts in the social
sciences and possibly beyond—without crossing disciplinary boundaries.
However, the integrated approach seeks to expand on such approaches, by drawing systematically on key disciplines. Existing approaches often advance just one
perspective or model preferred by the analyst (Allison and Zelikow 1999; especially
13, 15–17; Byman and Pollack 2001; especially 107–114). The model will often vary
with the analyst, but we tend to assume that states try to carefully weigh the costs
and benefits of various options for dealing with the issue at hand, and then choose,
or try to choose, the best option that advances national interests (Allison and Zelikow 1999; especially 13, 15–17). We then tend to describe their behavior as if they
acted as a coordinated actor rather than as a combination of competing groups,
bureaucracies, committees, and individuals with their own interests, preferences,
and modes of behavior. This conception of government behavior is captured
explicitly in the state-centric version of what is called the rational actor model. It is
drawn from the study of IR, with some basis in economics.
Such mono-theoretical explanations based fundamentally on the rational actor
model can certainly illuminate government behavior. They are important building blocks to more complex explanations. And in some cases, they may capture
enough of what is vital to be satisfactory. But they can also be misleading or
incomplete,9 if they seek to force reality into prefitted boxes. The rational actor
model derives chiefly from political science as applied to states, but could be
cross-fertilized better with other disciplines to explain foreign policy behavior.
The point of making greater use of political psychology is developed by
McDermott, Wernimont, and Koopman (2011).
The perspectives used in the integrated approach are chosen because, as
Table 1 suggests, they cover basic aspects of government behavior and offer
alternative and sometimes competing explanations.10 Using these five perspectives yields five different explanations for the same government behavior, in
Rashomon style.
8
Thaler is viewed as one of the founders of this field. In recent years, he has worked with scholars such as Cass
Sunstein and Daniel Kahneman to illuminate how economic theory can be made more robust if it accounts for
how people actually behave, given cognitive and psychological factors. On this genre, see their latest work (Thaler
and Sunstein 2008).
9
Allison offered one of the first challenges to the rational actor model on the basis of domestic political
processes. On the revision of this work, see Allison and Zelikow (1999).
10
The term ‘‘perspective’’ downplays pretension to theory insofar as it does not necessarily connote the ability
to generate or falsify predictions, while not precluding the potential for doing so.
111
Steve Yetiv
TABLE 1. Perspectives Within the Integrated Approach
Level of analysis
Goal or result
Decision making
Disciplines
Maximize perceived
national interests
Simplify reality and
decision making
Cost ⁄ benefit
analysis
Schema ⁄
analogies ⁄ biases
Domestic
politics model
Unitary actor ⁄
strategic context
Human mind ⁄
information
processing
Politicians ⁄
domestic politics
Meet domestic
objectives
Groupthink
Group chiefly
Government
politics model
Individual in
committee
setting
Likely defective
decision making
Push agency
interests ⁄ generate
collage
Constrained by
domestic
concerns
Group dynamics
Political science ⁄
economics
Cognitive
psychology ⁄
history
Political science ⁄
philosophy
Rational actor
model
Cognitive
Bargaining ⁄
conflict
Sociology
Political science ⁄
business
The five perspectives are based on different assumptions about what level of
analysis is most crucial (level of analysis) in explaining government behavior;
what are the direct or indirect goals or results of the behavior of the central
actor posited in the perspective (goal or result); and how that actor makes decisions consciously or subconsciously (decision making). For each case in question, we would start off by offering a rational actor model explanation of the
behavior we seek to examine and then move to offer competing explanations.
In contrast to the rational actor model, the cognitive approach offers a different explanation or part of an explanation for government behavior by focusing
on the minds of decision makers. Drawn from psychology and tied to history, it
assumes that individuals consciously or subconsciously use mental shortcuts, like
analogies to historical events, to simplify reality in order to facilitate decision
making (Khong 1992). As pointed out at greater length by McDermott, Wernimont, and Koopman (2011), cognitive approaches can complement or challenge
rationalist explanations.
The domestic politics model highlights how government behavior is shaped by
leaders who construct reality to meet their own domestic-level goals at least as
much if not more than national objectives. Unlike the other models, this model,
drawn from political science and from philosophy’s contribution to constructivism, assumes that leaders are concerned with their position, influence, and reputation in the domestic realm.
By contrast, the social psychology theory of groupthink focuses on the impact
of group dynamics on decision making, on the pressures for individuals in
groups to conform. It offers its own unique take on government behavior. For
its part, the bureaucratic politics model, drawn from political science and business, centers chiefly on individuals within a committee setting who bargain with
others and take positions driven by the interests and politics of their respective
fiefdoms. Seeing government behavior through the bureaucratic lens highlights
other possible explanations for how decisions were made.
The integrated approach allows for integration of insights between two disciplines or more. For instance, the application of the cognitive approach can illuminate historical cases and, in turn, inform explanations of foreign policy
action. It can help assess how analogies impact upon decision making. In turn,
that can help in assessing if and how analogical reasoning complements or challenges rational actor model explanations.
Integrating insights into one account can yield better explanations of events,
but the approach also allows for more complex integration across areas that are
112
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
often treated separately. The different perspectives carry some irreconcilable
assumptions, but when used in combination as cuts on reality, they allow for
integration of domestic and international relations theory and variables. This is
because the rational actor model is an IR theory of how states interact, while the
other four perspectives are foreign policy theories that feature domestic-level
variables.
The integrated approach also allows for integrating the three key areas of foreign policy: process, choice, and outcome. The rational actor model is designed
to explain just one of the two central dimensions of decision making—‘‘choice.’’
In basic terms, it tells us how actors choose. It tells us that when faced with a
choice between alternatives, actors will take (or try to take) the option that
promises the best outcome. But it ignores process or the nature, content, and
origin of the beliefs, perceptions, preferences, and objectives of actors. Process is
what happens in decision making prior to choice or to choosing among options.
The rational actor model treats these elements of process as a given and then
tells us how choices will be made. They are assumed rather than established
through research and analysis. But what if, for instance, we seek to understand
how actors form their preferences in the first place, or in other words, why they
prefer certain policies over others, such as free trade over protectionism, economic sanctions over negotiation, and war over economic sanctions.
All of the non-rational actor model perspectives offer insight at different levels
of analysis into preference formation—a key aspect of process. The integrated
approach shows how analogies can be a source of preferences, how certain policies are preferred because they accommodate the historical lesson or message
provided by the analogy. Others are less preferred because they clash with the
lesson or message of the analogy—something that historical study can help flesh
out. The analogy acts as a prism through which preferences can be formed,
downgraded in importance, and even rejected if the analogy is powerful in its
impact.
The domestic politics model assumes that preferences cannot simply be presumed to be national and largely invariant. They may arise from the personal
interests of leaders or organizations. It also suggests that preferences can form
as a function of the discursive environment created by decision makers who seek
to construct the adversary, but in the process alter that environment as well. The
environment, then, can push leaders to prefer certain policies over others.
While the domestic politics model highlights preference formation, group
dynamics can as well. The theory of groupthink assumes that group preferences
will form early in an event. This occurs largely through group dynamics driven
in part by a partial group leader whose preferences can prevail in part because
of groupthink dynamics.
Moreover, the bureaucratic politics model illuminates factors that may shape
each player’s perceptions, preferences, and likely course of action. It informs us
that preferences will be derived based on the bureaucracies from which individuals hail and from bargaining among individuals. These interests, in competition,
may ultimately shape the international behavior of actors more than concern for
perceived national interests.
Generating and Exploring Propositions
The integrated approach generates propositions that can further our understanding about how to integrate domestic and IR theory and variables; to integrate process, choice, and outcome in the study of foreign policy; and to
integrate insights from different disciplines. A few, basic hypotheses may illustrate this notion, starting with one that involves history, followed by others that
involve other disciplines.
Steve Yetiv
113
Proposition 1: Analogizing back to a historic event that induces fear among decision
makers will increase the potential for groupthink. (Reasoning: it will generate stress that is
linked to groupthink.)
Proposition 2: Strategic interactions that resemble non-iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma are
more likely to generate groupthink. (Reasoning: the external threat will be higher in a noniterated situation where cooperation is lower, and groupthink in theory is more likely when
the external threat is higher.)
Proposition 3: The higher the level of government politics (bargaining and rivalry among
committee members who represent particular departments and agencies) in a government,
the less bargaining leverage that government will have at the interstate level on the issue
being addressed by the committee. (Reasoning: it will be harder to generate resolve at the
interstate level with greater politics and rivalry at the domestic level.)
The first two propositions are in line with positions advocated by McDermott,
Wernimont, and Koopman (2011) that we must do more in international
studies to explore the impact of stress and other psychological factors. And
these propositions link different levels of analysis and draw upon different disciplines to highlight possible causality. The first requires an understanding of history and cognition as it relates to a past event. The second requires an
understanding of strategic interaction between actors at the international level
and the impact of such interaction on group behavior at the domestic level.
The third proposition bridges foreign policy theory (the government politics
model from political science and business) with IR theory (bargaining, strategic
interaction, game theory). The division of foreign policy and IR theory, while
sometimes useful for research, may also be bridged profitably in a systematic
manner.
History has another role in the integrated approach presented herein. It
involves presenting different theory-driven perspectives of the same government
behavior but also testing them. Thus, we may argue that the decision making
of President George W. Bush in the 1990–91 Persian Gulf crisis, which was triggered by Iraq’s August 2, 1990 invasion of Kuwait, was influenced by the
Munich analogy especially given that he participated in World War II. Exploring such a notion would require not only a good historical understanding of
the Persian Gulf crisis, but also of the period of the Munich analogy (See Yetiv
2004, 2011).
Such tests of the present perspectives cannot easily be conducted with statistics
or other quantitative approaches, though more specific hypotheses derived from
the integrated approach may be amenable to that kind of assessment. As such,
part of the testing needs to be done with detailed case studies either drawn from
the work of historians or conducted by non-historians with an appreciation for
the importance of understanding history.
Conclusion
This essay started by examining what history can contribute to IR. It argued that
history is most useful to IR in the study of short- and long-run change, as well as
in testing IR theories, but that the usefulness of history for IR depended on the
type of history and the type of IR in question and on how history was used. In
this sense, the great diversity of thought within both fields on issues of method,
theory, and empirics, and on what is most critical for scholars to study makes it
difficult to evaluate them with a broad brush. The real question then becomes:
what history and for what IR?
The essay addressed a second, larger question about how to enhance interdisciplinary work in the IS, including but moving beyond history and IR. The essay
114
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
offered the idea of integrated approaches and presented a particular kind of
integrated approach aimed at the study of government behavior, an approach
that is flexible and could include fewer or different perspectives as well (for
more details on the approach, see Yetiv 2004, 2011).
While this essay considered government behavior, I would also argue that such
integrated approaches are worthy of consideration in other areas that are interdisciplinary by nature. An example would be the study of transnational issues,
such as terrorism, energy, or the environment (see Anderson et al. 2008). These
areas are hard to study from any one disciplinary angle, although each discipline
can additionally illuminate them in its own right. Energy, for instance, involves
at a minimum political science, economics, history, business, and science. And,
as it stands, there is little work on energy that draws on multiple disciplines,
much less in a systematic nature that spells out how the disciplinary perspectives
can be used to illuminate an issue and to advance understanding. Quite the contrary, few articles on energy appear in major journals, and scholars and government analysts tend to be stove-piped in their respective areas. Integrated
approaches can sensibly bring them and their insights together. Integrative
approaches can help in doing so and can help ensure that critical dimensions of
a problem—such as technology (see Fritsch, 2011) are not ignored in theory or
in practice. As such, integrated approaches can help not only in academic
pursuits but also in problem solving in an interconnected world that requires
multiple ways of understanding and solving problems.
References
Abbott, Andrew. (2001) Time Matters: On Theory and Method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Allison, Graham, and Philip Zelikow. (1999) Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis,
2nd edition. New York: Longman.
Amenta, Edwin. (2003) What We Know about the Development of Social Policy: Comparative and
Historical Research in Comparative and Historical Perspective. In Comparative and Historical
Analysis, edited by Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and James Mahoney. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Anderson, Sheldon, Jeanne A.K. Hey, Mark Allen Peterson, Stanley W. Toops, and Charles
Stevens. (2008) International Studies: An Interdisciplinary Approach to Global Issues. Boulder:
Westview Press.
Appleby, Joyce Oldham, Lynn Hunt, and Margaret Jacob. (1994) Telling the Truth About History.
New York: W.W. Norton and Co.
Ariely, Dan. (2008) Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces That Shape Our Decisions. New York:
Harper Collins Publishers.
Ariely, Dan. (2010) The Upside of Irrationality: The Unexpected Benefits of Defying Logic at Work and at
Home. New York: Harper Collins Publishers.
Art, Robert J. (2003) A Grand Strategy for America. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Bartleson, Jens. (1995) A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bearman, Peter S., James Moody, and Robert Faris. (2002) Networks and History. Complexity 8:
61–71.
Bennett, Andrew, and Colin Elman. (2007) Case Study Methods in the International Relations
Subfield. Comparative Political Studies 40 (2): 170–195.
Bennett, Andrew, and Alexander George. (2005) Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social
Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Berkhofer, Robert F. Jr. (2008) Fashioning History: Current Practices and Principles. New York:
Palgrave.
Berlin, Isaiah. (1953) The Hedgehog and the Fox: An Essay on Tolstoy’s View of History. London:
Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Biersteker, Thomas, and Cynthia Weber. (1996) State Sovereignty as Social Construct. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Blyth, Mark M. (2002) Great Transformations: Economic Ideas and Institutional Change in the Twentieth
Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Steve Yetiv
115
Bommes, Michael, and Ewa Morawska. Eds. (2005) International Migration Research: Constructions,
Omissions and the Promises of Interdsciplinarity. London: Ashgate.
Box-Steffensmeier, Janet, Henry Brady, and David Collier. Eds. (2008) The Oxford Handbook of
Political Methodology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Braudel, Fernand. (1972) La Me´diterrane´e et le Monde Me´diterrane´en à l’Epoque de Philippe II (1949) [The
Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II]. New York: Harper.
Brecher, Michael. (1999) International Studies in the Twentieth Century and beyond: Flawed
Dichotomies, Synthesis, Cumulation. International Studies Quarterly 43 (2): 213–264.
Breisach, Ernst. (2007) Historiography: Ancient, Medieval, and Modern. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Burbank, Jane, and Frederick Cooper. (2010) Empires in World History: Power and the Politics of
Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Byman, Daniel L., and Kenneth M. Pollack. (2001) Let Us Now Praise Great Men: Bringing the
Statesman Back In. International Security 25 (4): 107–146.
Campbell, Donald T. (1988) Methodology and Epistemology for Social Sciences. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Carr, E. H. (1964) What is History? New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Christensen, Thomas. (1997) Perceptions and Alliances in Europe, 1865-1940. International
Organization 51 (4): 65–97.
Clark, Ian. (2007) International Legitimacy and World Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clemens, Elisabeth S. (2007) Toward a Historicized Sociology: Theorizing Events, Processes, and
Emergence. Annual Review of Sociology 33: 527–549.
Crawford, Neta. (2002) Argument and Change in World Politics. Cambridge Studies in International
Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Crouch, Colin, and Henry Farrell. (2004) Breaking the Path of Institutional Development:
Alternatives to the New Determinism in Political Economy. Rationality and Society 16: 5–43.
Dai, Xinyuan. (2007) International Institutions and National Policies. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Denemark, Robert A. (2010) The International Studies Encyclopedia. New York: Wiley & Sons.
Doyle, Michael W. (1986) Empires. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Elman, Colin, and Miriam F. Elman. Eds. (2001) Bridges and Boundaries: Historians, Political
Scientists, and the Study of International Relations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Elman, Colin, and Miriam Fendius Elman. (2008) The Role of History in International Relations.
Journal of International Studies 37: 357–364.
Ferguson, Niall. (2003) Empire: The Rise and Demise of the British World Order and the Lesson for Global
Power. New York: Basic Books.
Ferguson, Yale H., and Richard W. Mansbach. (2008) Polities Past and Present. Millennium
Journal 37: 365–381.
Fritsch, Stefan. (2011) Technology and Global Affairs. International Studies Perspectives 12 (1): 27–45.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (1982) Strategies of Containment: A Critical Appraisal of American National Security
Policy during the Cold War. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (2001) In Defense of Particular Generalization: Rewriting Cold War History,
Rethinking International Relations Theory. In Bridges and Boundaries: Historians, Political
Scientists, and the Study of International Relations, edited by Colin Elman, and Miriam Fendius
Elman. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (2002) The Landscape of History: How Historians Map and Past. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
George, Alexander L. (1993) Bridging the Gap: Theory and Practice in Foreign Policy. Washington, DC:
United States Institute of Peace Press.
Gilpin, Robert. (1981) War and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goldstein, Joshua. (1988) Long Cycles: Prosperity and War in the Modern Age. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Goldstone, Jack A. (2003) Comparative Historical Analysis and Knowledge Accumulation in the
Study of Revolutions. In Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, edited by James Mahoney and Dietrich Rueschemeyer. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Harvey, Frank P., and Michae Brecher, Eds. (2002) Critical Perspectives in International Studies. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Heisler, Martin O. (2008) Challenged Histories and Collective Self-Concepts: Politics in History,
Memory, and Time. The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 617 (1):
199–211.
116
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
Held, David, and Anthony G. McGrew. (2002) Globalization ⁄ Anti-Globalization. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Herring, George C. (2008) From Colony to Superpower: U.S. Foreign Relations since 1776. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hobsbawm, E. J. (1962) The Age of Revolution: Europe, 1789–1848. London: Weidenfeld and
Nicolson.
Hobson, John M., and George Lawson. (2008) What is History in International Relations?.
Millenium: Journal of International Studies 37: 415–435.
Holsti, Kalevi J. (2004) Taming the Sovereigns: Institutional Change in International Politics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Hui, Victoria Tin-bor. (2005) War and State Formation in Ancient China and Early Modern Europe.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ikenberry, G. John. (2001) After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint, and the Rebuilding of Order after
Major War. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
James, Patrick. (2002) International Relations and Scientific Progress: Structural Realism Reconsidered.
Columbus: Ohio State University Press.
Jervis, Robert. (1997) System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Kammen, Michael. (2008) The American Past Politicized: Uses and Misuses of History. The ANNALS
of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 617 (1): 42–57.
Kaufman, Stuart, Richard Little, and William Wohlforth, Eds. (2007) The Balance of Power in
World History. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Keene, Edward. (2008) The English School and British Historians. Journal of International Studies 37:
381–393.
Kennedy, Paul. (1987) The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers: Economic Change and Military Conflict from
1500 to 2000. New York: Random House.
Keohane, Robert O. (1984) After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Keohane, Robert O., and Lisa L. Martin. (1995) The Promise of Institutionalist Theory.
International Security 20 (1): 39–51.
Keohane, Robert O., and Joseph S. Nye. (2001) Power and Interdependence, 3rd edition. Boston:
Scott, Foresman and Co.
Khong, Yuen Foon. (1992) Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu and the Vietnam Decision of
1965. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
King, Gary, and Langche Zeng. (2007) When Can History Be our Guide? The Pitfalls of
Counterfactual Inference. International Studies Quarterly 51: 183–210.
King, Gary, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba. (1994) Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific
Inference in Qualitative Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Klabbers, Jan. (2009) The Bridge Crack’d: A Critical Look at Interdisciplinary Relations.
International Relations 23: 119–125.
Kugler, Jacek, and A. F. K. Organski. (1989) The Power Transition: A Retrospective and
Prospective Evaluation. In Handbook of War Studies, edited by Manus I. Midlarksky. Boston:
Unwin Hyman.
Larson, Deborah Welch. (2001) Sources and Methods in Cold War History: The Need for a New
Theory-Based Archival Approach. In Bridges and Boundaries, edited by Colin Elman, and Miriam
F. Elman. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lawson, George. (2006) The Promise of Historical Sociology in International Relations. International Studies Review 8 (3): 397–423.
Lawson, George. (2007) Historical Sociology in International Relations: Open Society, Research
Programme and Vocation. International Politics 44: 343–368.
Layne, Christopher. (2006) The Peace of Illusions: American Grand Strategy from 1940 to the Present.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Lebow, Richard Ned. (1988) Interdisciplinary Research and the Future of Peace and Security Studies. Political Psychology 9: 507–525.
Legro, Jeffrey W. (2007) Rethinking the World: Great Power Strategies and International Order. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Levy, Jack S. (1997) Prospect Theory, Rational Choice, and International Relations. International
Studies Quarterly 41: 87–112.
Lijphart, Arend. (1971) Comparative Politics and the Comparative Method. American Political Science
Review 65: 682–693.
Steve Yetiv
117
Little, Richard. (1999) Historiography and International Relations. Review of International Studies
25: 291–300.
Lustick, Ian. (1996) History, Historiography, and Political Science: Multiple Historical Records and
the Problem of Selection Bias. American Political Science Review 90: 605–618.
Lynn, John. A. (2001) Reflections on the History and Theory of Military Innovation and Diffusion.
In Bridges and Boundaries: Historians, Political Scientists, and the Study of International Relations,
edited by Colin Elman, and Miriam Fendius Elman. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
MacDonald, Paul K. (2009) Those Who Forget Historiography Are Doomed to Republish It:
Empire, Imperialism and Contemporary Debates about American Power. Review of International
Studies 35: 45–67.
Mahoney, James, and Dietrich Rueschmeyer. Eds. (2003) Comparative Historical Analysis in the
Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Maier, Charles S. (2006) Among Empires: American Ascendancy and Its Predecessors. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Maoz, Zeev. (2006) Network Polarization, Network Interdependence, and International Conflict,
1816-2002. Journal of Peace Research 43 (4): 391–411.
Martin, Lisa L., and Beth A. Simmons. (1998) Theories and Empirical Studies of International
Institutions. International Organization 52: 729–757.
McDermott, Rose. (2004) Political Psychology in International Relations. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press.
McDermott, Rose, Nicole Wernimont, and Cheryl Koopman. (2011) Applying Psychology to
International Studies: Challenges and Opportunities in Examining Traumatic Stress. International Studies Perspectives 12 (2): 119–135.
Mearsheimer, John J. (2001) The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: Norton.
Mintz, A., Ed. (2003) Integrating Cognitive and Rational Theories of Foreign Policy Decision Making: The
Polyheuristic Theory of Decision. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Mintz, Alex, and Karl DeRouen. (2010) Understanding Foreign Policy Decision Making. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Modelski, George, and William Thompson. (1996) Leading Sectors and World Powers: The Coevolution
of Global Economics and Politics. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.
Neustadt, Richard E., and Ernest R. May. (1986) Thinking in Time: The Uses of History for
Decision-Makers. New York: The Free Press.
Nexon, Daniel. (2009) The Struggle for Power in Early Modern Europe: Religious Conflict, Dynastic Empires,
and International Change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Nye, Joseph S. Jr. (1990) Bound to Lead: The Changing Nature of American Power. New York: Basic Books.
Nye, Joseph S. Jr. (2009) Understanding International Conflicts: An Introduction to Theory and History.
New York: Longman.
O’Reilly, Marc J. (2008) Unexceptional: America’s Empire in the Persian Gulf, 1941-2007. Lanham, MD:
Lexington Books.
Pelz, Stephen. (2001) Toward a New Diplomatic History: Two and a Half Cheers for International
Relations Methods. In Bridges and Boundaries, edited by Colin Elman, and Miriam F. Elman.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Philpott, Daniel. (2001) Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern International Relations.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Pierson, Paul. (2003) Big, Slow-Moving, and…Invisible: Macrosocial Processes in the Study of
Comparative Politics. In Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, edited by James
Mahoney, and Dietrich Rueschemeyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Porter, Bernard. (2006) Empire and Superempire: Britain, America and the World. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Renshon, Stanley Allen, and Peter Suedfeld, Eds. (2007) Understanding the Bush Doctrine:
Psychology and Strategy in the Age of Terrorism. New York: Routledge.
Reus-Smit, Christian. (2008) Reading History through Constructivist Eyes. Millennium: Journal of
International Studies 37: 395–415.
Rose, Gideon. (1998) Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy. World Politics 51: 144–172.
Rosenau, James N. (1997) Along the Domestic-Foreign Frontier: Exploring Governance in a Turbulent World.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rosenau, James N. (2003) Distant Proximities: Dynamics beyond Globalization. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Russett, Bruce M., and John R. Oneal. (2001) Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and
International Organizations. New York: W. W. Norton.
118
History, International Relations, and Integrated Approaches
Sarkees, Meredith Reid, and Marie T. Henehan. (2010) International Studies as a Discipline and
Women’s Status Therein. Denemark: The International Studies Encyclopedia.
Schroeder, Paul W. (1997) History and International Relations Theory: Not Uses or Abuses, but Fit
or Misfit. International Security 22: 64–74.
Schroeder, Paul W. (2004) Systems, Stability, and Statecraft, edited and with an Introduction by David
Wetzel, Robert Jervis, and Jack S. Levy. New York: Palgrave ⁄ Macmillan.
Schweller, Randall L. (2003) The Progressiveness of Neoclassical Realism. In Progress in International
Relations Theory, edited by Colin Elman, and Miriam Fendius Elman. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Slaughter, Anne-Marie Slaughter, Andrew S. Tulumello, and Stepan Wood. (1998)
International Law and International Relations Theory: A New Generation of Interdisciplinary
Scholarship. The American Journal of International Law 92: 367–397.
Taylor, A. J. P. (1954) The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 1848–1918. The Series: Oxford History of Modern
Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Taylor, A. J. P. (1965) English History, 1914-1945. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tetlock, Philip E., and Aaron Belkin, Eds. (1996) Counterfactual Thought Experiments in World
Politics: Logical, Methodological, and Psychological Perspectives. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Thaler, Richard H., and Cass R. Sunstein. (2008) Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth,
and Happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Thelen, Kathleen. (1999) Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics. Annual Review of
Political Science 2: 369–404.
Thelen, Kathleen. (2005) How Institutions Evolve. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, Julie. (2005) Humanities, Culture, and Interdisciplinarity: The Changing American Academy.
New York: State University of New York Press.
Tilly, Charles. (1995) To Explain Political Processes. American Journal of Sociology 100: 1594–1610.
Waltz, Kenneth. (1979) Theory of International Politics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Welch, David A. (2005) Painful Choices: A Theory of Foreign Policy Change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Wendt, Alexander. (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Yetiv, Steve A. (2004; 2nd edition 2011). Explaining Foreign Policy: U.S. Decision-Making & the Persian
Gulf Wars. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
Zak, Paul J., and Jacek Kugler. (2011) Neuroeconomics and International Studies: A New Understanding of Trust. International Studies Perspectives 12 (2): 136–151.
Copyright of International Studies Perspectives is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be
copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written
permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.
Purchase answer to see full
attachment