PLATO
INTRODUCTION
RICHARD KRAUT
Plato (427-347 BCE) was born into an aristocratic and wealthy Athenian family, and during
his early years he experienced the intellectual and political ferment of his time and place.
Many of the plays of Sophocles, Euripides, and Aristophanes were written during the last
quarter of the fifth century, and the moral and political conflicts they dramatized for their
fellow Athenians became his problems as well. Plato's youth also roughly coincided with the
Peloponnesian War (431-404), which ended in the defeat of democratic Athens at the hands
of Sparta. At the close of the war, Sparta installed in Athens a government of thirty rulers
(called “Thirty Tyrants” by later generations), who were selected for their antidemocratic
sympathies. One of the most ruthless among them, Critias, was the cousin of Plato's mother;
another, Charmides, was her brother. Both appear as interlocutors in some of Plato's
dialogues.
Like many young people of his time, Plato fell under the spell of Socrates (469-399), an
Athenian philosopher whose way of life is vividly preserved in Plato's Apology. Socrates
wrote nothing and professed ignorance, but his suspicion that no one possesses moral
knowledge, and his conviction that we must spend our lives searching for it, inspired many
of his followers, Plato among them, to abandon their worldly ambitions and to live a philo-
sophical life.
The Thirty who had been installed by Sparta were overthrown and democracy was re-
stored in 403; but a few years later, in 399, Socrates was brought to trial and found guilty of
not believing in the city's gods, of introducing new gods, and of corrupting the young. Some
scholars believe that the prosecution of Socrates was motivated partly by the perception that
he was a danger to the restored democracy. It is noteworthy that Plato's account of the speech
Socrates gave in his own defense, the Apology (apologia means “defense"), contains both
antipopulist elements (31–32) and a reminder that Socrates disobeyed the Thirty (32). Evi-
dently, he could not easily be classified as a democrat or an antidemocrat. Similarly, in the
Crito, Socrates is described as a man so satisfied with the Athenian legal system that he has
hardly left the city's walls (52–53), and yet he insists that one should follow the commands
of an expert and pay no attention to the opinions of the many (47). But were not the laws of
democratic Athens an expression of the opinion of the many? Socrates does not explain the
basis for his high regard for Athenian law.
Still more perplexing is an apparent inconsistency between the willingness Socrates ex-
presses in the Apology to engage in various forms of disobedience and the arguments he
accepts in the Crito for obeying one's city and its laws. He tells the jury that he will obey the
god who has commanded him to philosophize rather than any orders they give him (29), and
1
PLATO
2
personified Laws of Athens, that he is subordinate to Athens as a child is to a parent or a
yet in the Crito he refuses to escape from jail because he accepts the idea, proposed by the
slave to a master (50-51). If Socrates is willing to disobey his jurors, then why is he not
It is unlikely that Plato means to portray Socrates as a muddled thinker. On the contrary,
equally willing to disregard their decision that he is to be punished by death?
the impression he means to create is that Socrates is a man of penetrating insight and great
provoke his readers into philosophical reflection. Just as his conversations with Socrates les
argumentative skill: The apparent difficulties in Socrates ideas are the devices Plato uses to
him to philosophy, so he uses Socrates in his works to produce the same effect in us. Plato's
dialogues create a sense of unfinished business: lines of thought are disrupted, and gaps in
the argument remain unfilled. It is often difficult to know what Plato intends, because he
never speaks in his own voice. He uses dramatic characters and portrays a clash of views
because he regards the written word as a stimulus to philosophical insight rather than as the
embodiment of wisdom.
We are told by ancient sources that after the death of Socrates in 399, Plato left Athens
and spent time in Sicily, North Africa, and Egypt. Several of the thinkers he visited were
associated with the Pythagorean school-a group of philosophers (named after the school's
sixth-century founder, Pythagoras) who held that the human soul is reborn into other
human and animal bodies after death. They were also intensely interested in the mathemat-
ical relationships (for example, in musical scales) that underlie many physical phenomena.
As Plato moved beyond such early works as the Apology and Crito, both of these Pythago-
rean ideas—the transformation of the soul in its many lives and the mathematical nature of
reality-came to the fore in his writings. When he returned to Athens in 387, he established
a school (called the “Academy," after the grove beyond the city walls that was sacred to the
hero Academos) devoted to the study of philosophical and scientific problems. Ancient
writers describe two further visits of Plato to Sicily, in 367 and 361, undertaken to influence
the course of Syracusan politics, both ending in failure. He remained the head of the Acad.
emy until his death in 347.
Although Socrates insists in the Apology that we cannot know what comes after death, in
the Phaedo (a dialogue in which he holds his final conversation, before drinking a poison
and dying) he presents a series of arguments for the immortality of the soul. One of the most
striking components of this dialogue and others that were written during this period is their
affirmation of the existence of a new kind of objective reality, which Socrates calls a "form"
or "idea." (Capital letters-"Form," "Idea"--are sometimes used to name these objects, al-
though this is not Plato's practice.) For example, the form of equality (Plato is thinking of
the mathematical relationship) is not something that can be observed by the senses, but it
exists nonetheless. It is an eternal and changeless object that can be known only by means of
reason. The equal objects we observe are in some way defective copies of the perfect form:
they are called equal because they somehow share in or participate in the form of equality.
Plato does not attempt to give a complete list of the forms, but he believes that many of the
words we use in mathematics ("triangle," "line," "two") and in evaluative discourse ("jus-
tice," "beauty," "good") are really names of these abstract objects. Whenever we speak, we
are referring to forms, though most people assume that they are merely talking about a visible
and perishable world. They are, Plato thinks, living in a dream world: they fail to realize that
3
TRODUCTION
what they observe is a mere appearance and that a greater reality-the world of the forms-
stands behind the appearances.
In The Republic (composed after the Apology, Crito, and Phaedo), Plato pursues a ques-
tion that lies at the heart of Socrates' life and death. Although Socrates was a man of the
highest moral integrity, he was thought to be so dangerous to his community that the major-
ity of a jury of 501 fellow citizens condemned him to die. Since just action sometimes leads
to death, since it can lie hidden from others and even be misinterpreted as injustice, does that
not cast the most serious doubt on its value? Plato's guiding assumption, which he inherits
from Socrates, is that no progress can be made in answering this question until we come to
a fuller understanding of what justice is. (The Greek word is dikaiosune; in some contexts,
its meaning is broader than that of our "justice" and encompasses any kind of right treatment
of others.) Book The Republic portrays a series of unsuccessful attempts to define jus-
tice. Socrates here plays the role of someone who lacks knowledge and whose mission it is
to reveal to others that they are equally ignorant. Although Thrasymachus, the most formi-
dable interlocutor Socrates faces, is eventually defeated in argument, he plays a crucial role
in the dialogue: any attempt to vindicate the life of a just person must address itself to the
cynicism and immorality that Thrasymachus represents. Plato seems to be saying, in effect,
that there is a Thrasymachus in all of us and that we can exorcise him only by means of a
philosophical inquiry as wide ranging as The Republic.
Starting with Book II, Socrates sheds his role as an ignorant inquirer who merely poses
problems for others. For the remainder of the dialogue, he becomes a systematic philosopher
who puts forward a grand theory about the nature of human beings, the ideal state, the soul,
mathematics, knowledge, and the highest realities. His main interlocutors (Glaucon and
Adeimantus-Plato's brothers) occasionally interact with him, but they play a role far differ-
ent from the ones assigned to Cephalus, Polemarchus, and Thrasymachus in Book I. The
strategy pursued throughout the remainder of The Republic is to exploit the fact that it is not
merely individuals who can be characterized as just or unjust. We also use these terms to
praise or discredit certain forms of government. Perhaps, then, we can grasp the nature of
justice by asking what leads to the existence of a political community and what the justice
of such a community consists in. This attempt to construe political and individual justice as
the same property eventually leads to the proposal that justice consists in each part of a thing
doing its own activity. In a just city or state, each position is filled by a person who is quali-
fied to contribute to the good of the whole community. Similarly, in a just human being, each
part of the soul operates in a way that best serves the whole human being.
By the end of Book IV, Socrates seems to be on the verge of completing his demonstra-
tion of the great value of justice-but, in a sense, his argument has only begun. The institu-
tions of the ideal city--particularly abolition of the traditional family among rulers and
eugenic sharing of sexual partners-have not yet been fully discussed. Plato's aim is to
foster the greatest possible unity in the city, and he is willing to go to the greatest lengths to
guarantee that his citizens owe their strongest allegiance to each other, rather than to blood
relatives. But the topic that looms largest in Books V, VI, and VII is the proposal that the
best political community is one that gives complete authority to rigorously trained and mor-
ally flawless philosophers. Strictly speaking, the only real philosophers are those whose
understanding of value is based on their study of the forms, and in particular the form of the
PLATO
"good.” Socrates refrains from saying how good is to be defined, and in this sense the entire
project of the Republic is radically incomplete. But he seems to be suggesting that goodness
has a mathematical nature: that is why it is so important that philosophers first be trained as
mathematicians before they undertake the study of the highest form.
The dialogue reaches its culminating point with its depiction of the philosopher, for he or
she is the human being of perfect justice. The search for the value of justice” has led to the
conclusion that this virtue is most fully present in those who understand the nature of the
highest realities. Justice is the greatest good because the best sort of life is one in which
the structure of one's soul is guided by one's love and understanding of the most valuable
and real objects there are—the forms. Books VIII and IX round out Plato's argument by
portraying the diseased political structures and fragmented psychologies that arise when
worldly values—the love of honor, domination, wealth, and sexual pleasure—take priority
over all others. In Book X, the peripheral and external rewards of justice, having been dis-
missed in Book II, are allowed to return and provide the finishing touches on Socrates'
portrait of justice. Since the soul (or at least the rational part of it) does not perish, the good
of justice does not come to an end when the body perishes. By postponing the question of
posthumous existence to the end of The Republic, Socrates leads us to see that a life of jus-
tice would be worth living even if there were no afterlife.
Essays on many aspects of Plato's thought can be found in Richard Kraut, The Cam-
bridge Companion to Plato (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), and in Gail
Fine's two volumes, Plato 1 and Plato 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999). Full dis-
cussions of the Apology are provided by Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith,
Socrates on Trial (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1989), and C. D. C. Reeve,
Socrates in the Apology (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989). Detailed analysis of the Crito is pre-
sented by Richard Kraut, Socrates and the State (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1989), and Roslyn Weiss, Socrates Dissatisfied (New York: Oxford University Press,
1998). For studies of the Republic, see Julia Annas, An Introduction to Plato's Republic
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), Nicholas P. White, A Companion to Plato's Republic (In-
dianapolis: Hackett, 1979), C. D. C. Reeve, Philosopher-Kings (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press, 1988), and Richard Kraut, Plato's Republic: Critical Essays (Lanham,
Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1997). The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political
Thought, edited by Christopher Rowe and Malcolm Schofield, in association with Simon
Harrison and Melissa Lane (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), contains seven
chapters on Plato's politics.
Defence of Socrates
17a
18a
b
b
I don't know how you, fellow Athenians, have
been affected by my accusers, but for my part
I felt myself almost transported by them, so
persuasively did they speak. And yet hardly a
word they have said is true. Among their many
falsehoods, one especially astonished me: their
warning that you must be careful not to be
taken in by me, because I am a clever speaker.
It seemed to me the height of impudence on
their part not to be embarrassed at being re-
futed straight away by the facts; once it became
apparent that I was not a clever speaker at
all-unless indeed they call a 'clever speaker
one who speaks the truth. If that is what they
mean, then I would admit to being an orator,
although not on a par with them.
As I said, then, my accusers have said little
or nothing true; whereas from me you shall
hear the whole truth, though not, I assure you,
fellow Athenians, in language adorned with
fine words and phrases or dressed up, as theirs
was: you shall hear my points made sponta-
neously in whatever words occur to me-
persuaded as I am that my case is just. None of
you should expect anything to be put differ-
ently, because it would not, of course, be at all
fitting at my age, gentlemen, to come before
you with artificial speeches, such as might be
composed by a young lad.
One thing, moreover, I would earnestly
beg of you, fellow Athenians. If you hear me
defending myself with the same arguments
I normally use at the bankers' tables in the
market-place (where many of you have heard
me) and elsewhere, please do not be surprised
or protest on that account. You see, here is the
reason: this is the first time I have ever
appeared before a court of law, although I am
over 70; so I am literally a stranger to the dic-
tion of this place. And if I really were a for-
eigner, you would naturally excuse me, were I
to speak in the dialect and style in which I had
been brought up; so in the present case as well
I ask you, in all fairness as I think, to disregard
my manner of speaking-it may not be as
good, or it may be better—but to consider and
attend simply to the question whether or not my
case is just; because that is the duty of a judge,
as it is an orator's duty to speak the truth.
To begin with, fellow Athenians, it is fair
that I should defend myself against the first set
of charges falsely brought against me by my
first accusers, and then turn to the later charges
and the more recent ones. You see, I have been
accused before you by many people for a long
time now, for many years in fact, by people
who spoke not a word of truth. It is those
people I fear more than Anytus and his crowd,
though they too are dangerous. But those
others are more so, gentlemen: they have taken
hold of most of you since childhood, and made
persuasive accusations against me, yet without
an ounce more truth in them. They say that
there is one Socrates, a 'wise man', who pon-
ders what is above the earth and investigates
everything beneath it, and turns the weaker
argument into the stronger.
Those accusers who have spread such
rumour about me, fellow Athenians, are the dan-
gerous ones, because their audience believes that
people who inquire into those matters also fail to
acknowledge the gods. Moreover, those accusers
с
с
d
From Defence of Socrates, Euthyphro, and Crito, translated by David Gallop. Copyright @ 1997 by Oxford University Press.
Reprinted by permission of the publisher and translator. The notes are the translator's.
5
Purchase answer to see full
attachment