No. 4
January 13, 2011
Constitutional Guidance for Lawmakers
Enough Is Enough:
Why General Welfare Limits Spending
Perhaps no other clause in the Constitution generated as much debate among the Founders as the “Spending
Clause”—the first of the 18 powers granted to Congress under Article I, Section 8. Alexander Hamilton and
James Madison, the principal authors of The Federalist, famously disagreed about the meaning of “general
Welfare” and the limits to Congress’s spending power. For the past 70 years, however, this fruitful debate
over the meaning of the Constitution has been replaced by the view that there are no limitations whatsoever
on Congress’s power to spend and that the “general Welfare” means whatever Congress says it means. Today,
no project is deemed too local or too narrow not to fall under the “general Welfare” rubric. It is therefore
incumbent upon Members of Congress to consider, once again, the limits of their spending power and recognize, as even Hamilton did, that it is not unlimited. This essay is adapted from The Heritage Guide to
the Constitution for a new series providing constitutional guidance for lawmakers.
“The Congress shall have Power To lay and collect Taxes, Duties, Imposts and
Excises, to pay the Debts and provide for the common Defence and general
Welfare of the United States.”
— Article I, Section 8, Clause 1
A
lthough the Spending Clause is the source of
congressional authority to levy taxes, it permits
the levying of taxes for two purposes only: to pay the
debts of the United States, and to provide for the common defense and general welfare of the United States.
Taken together, these purposes have traditionally been
held to imply and constitute the “Spending Power.”
To many today, those two purposes are so broad
as to amount to no limitation at all. The contemporary
view is that Congress’s power to provide for the “gen-
Published by
eral Welfare” is a power to spend for virtually anything that Congress itself views as helpful. To be sure,
some of the Founders, most notably Alexander Hamilton, supported an expansive spending power during
the Constitutional Convention; but such proposals,
including an explicit attempt to authorize spending
by the federal government for internal improvements,
were rejected by the Convention. Hamilton continued
to press his case by arguing during George Washington’s administration for an expansive interpretation of
214 Massachusetts Avenue, NE
Washington, DC 20002-4999
(202) 546-4400 • heritage.org
The Heritage Foundation’s First Principles Series explores the fundamental ideas of conservatism and the American political tradition.
For more information call 1-800-544-4843 or visit heritage.org/bookstore. Nothing written here is to be construed as necessarily reflecting the views of
The Heritage Foundation or as an attempt to aid or hinder the passage of any bill before Congress.
2
the clause (which Washington adopted). In his “Report
on Manufactures” (1791), Hamilton contended that
the only limits on the tax-and-spend power were the
requirements that duties be uniform, that direct taxes
be apportioned by population, and that no tax should
be laid on articles exported from any state. The power
to raise money was otherwise “plenary, and indefinite,” he argued, “and the objects to which it may be
appropriated are no less comprehensive.”
Hamilton’s broad reading met with opposition
from many of the other Founders. James Madison
repeatedly argued that the power to tax and spend did
not confer upon Congress the right to do whatever it
thought to be in the best interest of the nation, but only
to further the ends specifically enumerated elsewhere
in the Constitution, a position supported by Thomas
Jefferson.
There was also a third, more intermediate, interpretation, recognized later even by Alexander Hamilton. According to this view, the “common Defence
and general Welfare” language is not, as Madison
contended, a shorthand way of limiting the power to
tax and spend in furtherance of the powers elsewhere
enumerated in Article I, Section 8; but it does contain
its own limitation, namely, that spending under the
clause be for the “general” (that is, national) welfare
and not for purely local or regional benefit. President
James Monroe later adopted this position—albeit with
more teeth than Hamilton had been willing to give
it—in his 1822 message vetoing a bill to preserve and
repair the Cumberland Road. Monroe contended that
Congress’s power to spend was restricted “to purposes of common defence, and of general, national, not
local, or state, benefit.”
There are relatively few examples from the early
Congresses of debate over the scope of the spending
power, but the few that do exist are enlightening. The
First Congress refused to make a loan to a glass manufacturer after several Members expressed the view that
such an appropriation would be unconstitutional, and
the Fourth Congress did not believe it had the power
to provide relief to the citizens of Savannah, Georgia,
No. 4
after a devastating fire destroyed the entire city. The
debates do not reflect whether Congress thought such
appropriations unconstitutional because they did not
further other enumerated powers (Madison’s position)
or because they were of local rather than national benefit (Monroe’s position), but they reflect a rejection of
the broad interpretation of the spending power originally proffered by Hamilton.
Save for a brief interlude during the one-term
presidency of John Quincy Adams, the more
restrictive interpretation of spending power
was adopted by every President until the Civil
War.
On the other hand, some appropriations for
apparently local projects were approved, but it can
be argued that those projects were of general benefit
or specifically tied to other enumerated powers, and
hence within the authority conferred by Article I, Section 8. At the same time it was denying a request to
fund the dredging of the Savannah River, for example,
Congress approved an appropriation for a lighthouse
at the entrance of the Chesapeake Bay. Both measures
were important for navigation, but the lighthouse
was of benefit to the coastal trade of the entire nation
(and hence to interstate commerce), while the dredging operation was primarily of local, intrastate benefit
to the people of Georgia and hence fell on the “local”
rather than the “general” side of the public welfare line.
Congress approved various appropriations to fund
a road across the Cumberland Gap, but it rejected as
unconstitutional a larger appropriation for internal
improvements of which the Cumberland Gap road
project was a part. Congress accepted the view that
it had no power under the Constitution to open roads
and canals in any state; its power to fund the Cumberland Road was the result of the compact with Ohio
“for which the nation receive[d] an equivalent,” namely, Ohio’s promise not to tax for five years any lands
sold by the federal government in Ohio. Moreover, as
No. 4
George Washington had repeatedly urged while President, the opening of a road across the Cumberland
Gap was strategically necessary to keep the western
territories allied with the coastal states (rather than
with the foreign powers that controlled the Mississippi river region at the time), something critically important to the security of the entire nation and not just
the people of Ohio. The Cumberland Gap road was an
example of a local project that directly benefited the
nation. Appropriations for other local projects such as
public education and local roads and canals, the “general” benefit of which was less direct, were viewed as
unconstitutional, and a proposal in Jefferson’s 1806
State of the Union Address to amend the Constitution
to permit funding for such internal improvements was
never adopted.
In sum, although Alexander Hamilton and other
leaders of the Federalist Party argued for an expansive reading of the spending power, their reading was,
on the whole, rejected both by Congress and, after the
election of 1800, by the executive. Indeed, the differing
views on the scope of federal power was a principal
ground on which the 1800 presidential-election contest
between Jefferson and incumbent Federalist President
John Adams was waged. As Jefferson would note in an
1817 letter to Albert Gallatin, the different interpretations of the Spending Clause put forward by Hamilton, on the one hand, and Madison and Jefferson, on
the other, were “almost the only landmark which now
divides the federalists from the republicans.” Jefferson
won that election, and, save for a brief interlude during
the one-term presidency of John Quincy Adams, the
more restrictive interpretation of spending power was
adopted by every President until the Civil War.
President Madison vetoed as unconstitutional an
internal improvements bill that was passed by Congress at the very end of his presidency. President James
Monroe also rejected the expansive Hamiltonian view
of the Spending Clause (albeit on slightly different
grounds than Madison had), vetoing various attempts
at internal improvement bills during most of his two
terms. But in the last year of his presidency, James
3
Monroe, finding the line between “general” welfare
and local welfare a hard one to define, signed a few
bills to fund surveys for some local internal improvement projects. He thus opened a gate through which
flowed a flood of spending on local projects during
the administration of President John Quincy Adams.
But Adams’s resurrection of the Hamiltonian position
became the focus of the next presidential election, contributing to Adams’s defeat at the hands of Andrew
Jackson, who promptly put to rest “this dangerous
doctrine” by vetoing a $200 million appropriation for
the purchase of stock in the Maysville and Lexington
Turnpike Company and for the direct construction
of other “ordinary” roads and canals by the government itself. So strong was his veto message that for
four years Congress did not even try to pass another
such bill, and when in 1834 it passed an act to improve
the navigation of the Wabash River, Jackson again
responded forcefully, rejecting as a “fallacy” the contention that the Spending Clause conferred upon Congress the power to do whatever seemed “to conduce to
the public good.”
In 1847 and 1857, Presidents James K. Polk and
James Buchanan, respectively, vetoed subsequent congressional efforts to fund internal improvements. Polk
vetoed a bill strikingly similar to much of the porkbarrel legislation to which we have grown accustomed
in modern times. It provided $6,000 for projects in the
Wisconsin territory—constitutionally permissible
because of Congress’s broader powers over federal territories—but it also included $500,000 for a myriad of
projects in the existing states. Polk contended that to
interpret the Spending Clause to permit such appropriations would allow “combinations of individual and
local interests [that would be] strong enough to control
legislation, absorb the revenues of the country, and
plunge the government into a hopeless indebtedness.”
Similarly, in his message vetoing the college land
grant bill, President Buchanan took it as a given that
the funds raised by Congress from taxation were
“confined to the execution of the enumerated powers
delegated to Congress.” The idea that the resources
4
of the federal government—either taxes or the public
lands—could be diverted to carry into effect any measure of state domestic policy that Congress saw fit to
support “would be to confer upon Congress a vast and
irresponsible authority, utterly at war with the wellknown jealousy of Federal power which prevailed at
the formation of the Constitution.”
Thus, while there were clearly voices urging for an
expansive spending power before the Civil War, the
interpretation held by Jefferson, Madison, and Monroe is the one that prevailed for most of the first seventy years after adoption of the Constitution.
While the Court has recently restored some
limits to other powers delegated to Congress
(such as the Commerce Clause), it has not yet
done so with the Spending Power. This does
not prevent Congress from adopting on its own
a view of its power to spend that is more in
accord with those of the Founders.
Modern-day jurisprudence on the Spending Clause
begins with the 1936 New Deal-era case of United States
v. Butler. In that case, both parties relied upon the Hamiltonian position, despite the history recounted above.
Both the majority and dissenting opinions of the Court
facially accepted the correctness of Hamilton’s position even though the majority ruled that the particular
tax and regulatory program at issue in the case was
unconstitutional because its purpose was to regulate
and control agricultural production, “a matter beyond
the powers delegated to the federal government”—a
holding much more in line with Madison’s interpretation of the spending power than Hamilton’s.
Moreover, the Hamiltonian position purportedly
adopted by the Court was not the expansive view that
Congress could do whatever it deemed to be in the
public interest, but the much more limited view that
the limits on spending were contained in the Spending Clause itself and not in the remainder of Article
I, Section 8. “While, therefore, the power to tax is not
No. 4
unlimited,” Justice Owen J. Roberts wrote, “its confines
are set in the clause which confers it, and not in those
of Section 8 which bestow and define the legislative
powers of the Congress.” In other words, the only limitation on Congress’s power to tax and spend was that
the spending be for the “general Welfare”—the position actually advocated by James Monroe. What really
makes Butler a departure from the early interpretation
of the clause, then, was that it gave virtually unlimited
discretion to Congress to determine what was in the
“general welfare”—a holding that, practically speaking,
is much more in line with the expansive Hamiltonian
position than the positions advocated either by Monroe or by Madison and Jefferson.
Since Butler, the courts have essentially treated
whatever limitation the clause might impose as essentially a nonjusticiable political question. In the 1987
case of South Dakota v. Dole, for example, the Supreme
Court noted that “the level of deference to the congressional decision is such that the Court has more recently questioned whether ‘general welfare’ is a judicially
enforceable restriction at all.” Instead, the courts have
focused not on the constitutionality of spending programs themselves, but on whether various conditions
imposed on the receipt of federal funds—conditions
designed to achieve ends concededly not within Congress’s enumerated powers—were constitutionally
permissible. In South Dakota v. Dole, the Court adopted
a four-prong test against which it assesses the constitutionality of spending conditions: (1) the spending
power must be in pursuit of the “general Welfare,” a
requirement that the Court left to Congress’s judgment
to satisfy because, in its view, “the concept of welfare
or the opposite is shaped by Congress”; (2) whether the
conditions imposed were unambiguous; (3) whether
they were related to the particular national projects or
programs being funded (thus far, the Court has not
invalidated a spending restriction on the grounds that
it is too unrelated to the programs being funded); and
(4) whether there are other constitutional provisions
that provide an independent bar to the conditional
grant of federal funds. For example, Congress could
No. 4
not impose as a condition that a state receiving federal
funds for its welfare programs require welfare recipients to waive their Fourth Amendment rights.
Of these four requirements, the “relatedness” and
the independent constitutional bar prongs are the
only ones that at present have any prospect of actually
imposing a real limit on spending. Yet in the facts of
South Dakota v. Dole itself, the Court concluded that conditioning receipt of federal highway funds on a state’s
adoption of a twenty-one-year-old drinking age was
sufficiently related to the funding program. Eighteenyear-old residents of states with a twenty-one-year-old
drinking age would drive to border states where the
drinking age was eighteen and procure their liquor,
the argument went. When driving back, the drivers
had an increased risk of drunk driving on the highways paved by federal funds, and that was a sufficient
connection for the Court.
5
Both Justices William J. Brennan, Jr., and Sandra
Day O’Connor dissented. Justice O’Connor noted in
her South Dakota v. Dole dissent: “If the spending power
is to be limited only by Congress’ notion of the general
welfare, the reality...is that the Spending Clause gives
‘power to the Congress...to become a parliament of the
whole people, subject to no restrictions save such as
are self-imposed.’ This...was not the Framers’ plan and
it is not the meaning of the Spending Clause.”
While the Court has recently restored some limits to
other powers delegated to Congress (such as the Commerce Clause), it has not yet done so with the Spending
Power. This does not prevent Congress from adopting
on its own a view of its power to spend that is more in
accord with those of the Founders.
John C. Eastman is the Donald P. Kennedy Chair in Law
at Chapman University School of Law.
Purchase answer to see full
attachment