Final Paper - An Ethical Insight on Gender Pay Gap, philosophy homework help

User Generated

uheevxra31

Humanities

Description

Please read these assignment instructions before writing your paper, and re-read them often during and after the writing process to make sure that you are fulfilling all of the instructions. Please also utilize the assignment guidance and the outlined model provided.

Overview
In the Week One Assignment, you formulated a concrete ethical question, took a position on that topic, and identified a reason supporting and a reason opposing that position. In the Week Three Assignment, you discussed either deontological or utilitarian theory, applied that theory to the question, and raised a relevant objection.

By engaging with the course material, you now have had a chance to refine your thinking and broaden your understanding of the problem by approaching it from the perspective of multiple ethical theories.

In this paper, you will demonstrate what you have learned by writing an essay in which you

  • Present a revised formulation of the ethical question and introduction to the topic.
  • Explain the kind of reasoning you think is the best way to approach this question, and how that reasoning supports the position you think is strongest.
  • Raise an objection, and be able to respond to it.

Instructions
Write an essay that conforms to the requirements below. The paper must be 1500 to 2000 words in length (excluding the title and reference pages) and formatted according to APA style as outlined in the Ashford Writing Center (Links to an external site.)Links to an external site..

The paragraphs of your essay should conform to the following guidelines:

  • Introduction
    Your first paragraph should begin with the topic question, suitably revised. It should be focused, concrete, and on a relevant moral problem. You should then introduce the topic in the way described by the Week One instructions, but reflecting the developed understanding and information you have gained about the topic and any necessary refinement of the scope.

    Follow this with a thesis statement that states your position, and a brief description of the primary reason(s) supporting your position. (See the handout on thesis statements provided). Finally, provide a brief preview of the overall aim and procedure of your paper.
  • Explanation and Demonstration of Moral Reasoning
    This section of the Final Paper will explain and demonstrate what you believe to be the best way of reasoning about the question you have chosen, and showing how that reasoning supports the position you have taken on the question. You might explain the principles, rules, values, virtues, conceptions of purposes and ends, and other general ideas that you find persuasive, and show how they support concrete judgments.

    In the course of doing so, you must make reference to at least two of the approaches that we have examined in the course (such as deontological, utilitarian, or virtue-based), and utilize at least one resource off the provided list for each of the two approaches. One of these theories may be the theory you discussed in your Week Three Assignment, but your discussion here should be more refined.

    For example, you might find the reasoning associated with Aristotelian virtue ethics to be the most compelling, and reference Aristotle in the process of showing how that reasoning supports a certain conclusion. In the course of this, you could contrast that with a utilitarian approach, referencing Mill for instance.
  • Objection and Response
    After explaining the ethical reasoning that supports your position, you should raise an objection and respond to it. An objection articulates a plausible reason why someone might find the argument weak or problematic. You should explain how it brings out this weakness, and do so in a way that would be acceptable to someone who disagrees with your own argument. Then, provide the best response you can to the objection, showing how it does not undermine your position. Your response should not simply restate your original position or argument, but should say something new in support of it.
  • Conclusion
    Provide a conclusion that sums up what you presented in the paper and offers some final reflections.

Resource Requirement
You must use at least four scholarly resources. Two of the resources must be drawn from the list of acceptable primary resources on each of the two theories you discuss. For example, if you discuss deontology and virtue ethics, you would need at least one resource under the “Deontology” list and at least one resource under the “Virtue Ethics” list. The other two may be from either the Required or Recommended Resources, or scholarly resources found in the Ashford University Library.

  • The textbook may be cited, but it does not count toward the resource requirement. If you cite the textbook, you will still need to cite at least four more sources that fulfill the requirements stated above.
  • If you need help with finding additional resources, or are unsure about whether a particular resource will count toward the requirement, please contact your instructor.
  • For sources to count toward the resources requirement, they must be cited within the text of your paper and on the reference page. Sources that are listed on the references page, but not cited within the paper, do not count toward fulfilling the resources requirement.
  • For information regarding APA, including samples and tutorials, visit the Ashford Writing Center.

Unformatted Attachment Preview

Running head: GENDER PAY GAP 1 An Ethical Insight on Gender Pay Gap Kendran Thornton PHI 208 Ethics and Moral Reasoning Prof. Whitney Easton August 14, 2017 GENDER PAY GAP 2 An Ethical Insight on Gender Pay Gap One of the most important challenges that women in the United States still face is gender pay gap, as men earn on average around 20 percent less than man. Even when the gap is adjusted by taking into account differences such as occupations chosen, hours works, education, and job experience women still make almost 10 % less than men (Tharenou, 2013). In a society that seeks to achieve gender equality, the existence of a pay gap between men and women is clearly an ethical problem. While paying women less than men is unlawful, one might wonder whether it is unethical. The purpose of the present paper is to analyze whether the ethical theory of utilitarianism can be used to determine whether gender pay gap is an ethical dilemma and antigender discrimination laws can be defended by appealing to ethics. By analyzing the principles of utilitarianism, it is shown that gender pay gap is indeed an ethical dilemma because it produces both short- and long-term negative consequences that impact society as a whole. Theory Explanation According to the consequentialist perspective on ethics, moral values serve to the purpose of producing the right type of general consequences. In other words, consequentialism seeks to determine the moral value of an action by looking into the consequences of the action. For example, if the purpose of morality is to bring happiness, actions that seek to produce happiness for the highest number of people will be regarded as ethical actions. One well-known consequentialist approach is the utilitarianism of John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham (Haines, n.d.). In the perspective of John Stuart Mill “the basis of morals is utility or the greatest happiness principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong in proportion as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness” (Mill, n.d.). Mill GENDER PAY GAP 3 conceptualizes happiness as pleasure and the absence of pain; unhappiness obviously refers to pain in the absence of pleasure. In other words, John Stuart and other utilitarianists believe that pleasure and freedom from pain are the only desirable ends from any actions, which means actions are only ethically valid if they lead to general pleasure and freedom to pain. For example, if someone makes a charitable act through which fewer people are hungry, the action will be regarded as ethical by utilitarianists because it produces more happiness and less pain. On the other hand, if an individual obtains pleasure and frees himself or herself from pain at the expense of others, the action will not be regarded as ethical by utilitarianists because both pleasure and pain were produced as the result of the action. Utilitarianism can be differentiated into two categories: Act Utilitarianism and Rule Utilitarianism. According to Act Utilitarianism, determining whether an act of ethical or not will require looking at the consequences of a specific act. According to Rule Utilitarianism, on the other hand, one must look at “the bigger picture” in order to determine whether the consequences of an act are desirable or not (Tharenou, 2013). Theory Application Considering that the principles of utilitarianism promote actions that are based on consequences and that the desired consequences are those where the greatest happiness occurs, it can be inferred that the theory can be applied to determine whether the consequences that result from gender pay gap are ethical or not. For instance, if a company discriminates against an individual due to its gender, it risks losing a competent employee. This example can be analyzed from the perspective of Act utilitarianism by looking at the specific consequences of the discriminatory act. More specifically, if a company pays women less than men for the same job GENDER PAY GAP 4 through specific strategies that allows them to avoid being legally sanctioned, many female employees might decide searching job in a company that does not practice discrimination policies, for which the company will lose many valuable employees. In other words, such an action will not be beneficial for the company and it will likely lower the happiness of stakeholders. More so, the action will also lower the happiness of the employees who will have to leave their work and search for an employee. Considering that this particular action (paying female employees less) leads to specific negative consequences (lowering the level of happiness of stakeholders and many employees) it can be asserted that the company from the example will have committed an ethical violation from the Act utilitarianism perspective. From the Rule Utilitarianism perspective, on the other hand, it is necessary to look at the bigger picture in order to determine if discriminating female employees at work are ethical or not. For example, it can be argued that if companies continue to pay women less than men, there are long-term economic and social impacts of discrimination. Long-term consequences could include less educational and work opportunities for women and a generally less prepared workforce for an increasingly complex economy. In other words, practicing double standards at the workplace could also be considered unethical from the Rule Utilitarianism perspective. Objection Those who object to the validity of utilitarianism in ethically justifying anti-gender discrimination laws might point out several weak elements of the arguments presented above. For instance, from the perspective of Act Utilitarianism, it was argued that if a company pay women less than men this will bring negative consequences for both the company’s stakeholders and the employees. While this might be true in many circumstances, it is difficult to prove that GENDER PAY GAP 5 companies could not at times benefit from practicing employee discrimination. On the other hand, it is more difficult to argue against the positions which can be taken from the Rule Utilitarianism perspective. Even if individual companies could benefit from practicing discrimination based on gender (or other demographic variables), the society as a whole would not, as discriminatory practices benefit those who practice them for their own interests. For this reason, utilitarianism, especially when understood from the Rule perspective, can provide strong arguments against gender pay gap. Conclusion In conclusion, the present paper shows that gender pay gap is indeed an ethical dilemma when taken from an Utilitarianist perspective, as such a gap produces both short- and long-term negative consequences that impact society as a whole. From the perspective of Act Utilitarianism, it has been shown that discriminating female employees is unethical because such an action will harm the company and the employees. Such a discrimination is also unethical from the perspective of Rule Utilitarianism, as it can produce long-term economic and social problems for the society as a whole. Since utilitarianism can be used to show that gender discrimination at work in unethical, it can also be used to defend laws that seek to eliminate the gender pay gap. GENDER PAY GAP 6 References Haines, W. (n.d.). Consequentialism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/conseque/ Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism, in the original version in the textbook, or in the version by Jonathan Bennett. Retrieved from www.earlymoderntexts.com Tharenou, P. (2013). The work of feminists is not yet done: The gender pay gap—a stubborn anachronism. Sex roles, 68(3-4), 198-206. 61 Traditional of Ethics IntroducingTheories Philosophy Federico©Terry Caputo/iStock/Thinkstock Why/ Getty Images You have your way. I have my way. As for “It is the mark of an educated mind the right way, the correct way, and the only to be able to entertain a thought way, it does not exist. without accepting it” —Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra —Aristotle mos81165_06_c06.indd 175 1/6/14 2:33 PM CHAPTER 6 Section 6.1 How Should One Act? Learning Objectives After reading this chapter, students will be able to: 1. Characterize the classical theories of ethics—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics. 2. Identify some of the problems these theories confront. 3. Describe other metaethical views, such as relativism and egoism. 4. Apply ethical theories to problems that affect both individuals and larger groups, including environmental challenges. What We Will Discover • Philosophers have developed theories to provide support for our claims about right and wrong. • Other theories such as egoism and relativism offer alternatives to traditional theories of ethics. • Ethics has many specific applications to our lives, from the very personal and specific to those that affect everyone in society. 6.1 How Should One Act? E thics, or moral philosophy, investigates how we can evaluate our behavior in terms of right and wrong, good and bad—in other words, how we determine what we should do, what we should not do, and how to tell the difference. After looking at the three classical ethical views that philosophers have presented and some of the problems with these theories, we will explore some alternative approaches. Utilitarianism Suppose you and five of your friends are hanging out one night and decide to order a pizza. You are all equally hungry and decide to order two pizzas, each of which has six slices. Thus, when the pizzas are delivered, it is pretty easy to determine how to divide the pizzas in a way that is the fairest: Everyone gets two slices. It may be that one person wanted a third slice, and someone else may have only wanted one. Yet without knowing anything else, this arrangement, more than any other, will be the most beneficial to the greatest number of people. Photos.com/© Getty Images/Thinkstock Jeremy Bentham is associated with the founding of utilitarianism, which states that given a choice between two acts, the one that creates greater happiness for the greatest number of people should be chosen. This simple example demonstrates the basic notion at the heart of the ethical doctrine known as utilitarianism. Often associated with the philosophers Jeremy Bentham (1748–1822) and John Stuart Mill, utilitarianism offers a very straightforward and direct way to evaluate behavior. When given a choice between two acts, utilitarianism states that mos81165_06_c06.indd 176 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 the act that should be chosen is the one that creates the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of people. Philosophers (and economists) often use the term utility to express this quality. Utility is the satisfaction one gets from something. For instance, if you like chocolate ice cream more than vanilla ice cream, we can say that chocolate ice cream has a higher utility for you, relative to vanilla ice cream. In theory, at least, each of us can rank all of our choices according to a scale that indicates our relative preferences. Some philosophers, such as Bentham, even attempted to assign numbers to these preferences. If someone likes chocolate ice cream five times as much as vanilla ice cream, that person would presumably be willing to accept five vanilla ice cream cones as a substitute for one chocolate ice cream cone. It should also be noted that utility is regarded in terms of net utility: The correct moral choice is that which generates the greatest good and also minimizes unhappiness. Read more of John Stuart Mill’s ideas on this topic in his work Utilitarianism in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. Because utilitarianism considers an act’s consequences in assessing its morality, utilitarianism is also regarded as a consequentialist theory. The basic idea in consequentialism is to consider the consequences that will result from the choices one confronts: If the consequences of one act produce the greatest net good—or the highest utility—for the greatest number of people, this is the act one should carry out. Many people find this to be a rather obvious ethical viewpoint; clearly if we had decided to give all the pizza slices to just three people and no slices to the other three, this would seem rather unfair. It should also be clear that utilitarianism offers an approach to scenarios other than distributing pizza and ice cream. Imagine Mary really loves to dance, but she does not get to go dancing very often. Mary has three children, with whom she enjoys spending time and who enjoy spending time with her. One night she is given the option of staying home and spending time with her children or going dancing. What should she do? The utilitarian might argue that, on the one hand, the pleasure Mary gets from dancing is greater than staying with her children. Yet on the other hand, her children will receive great pleasure if she does not go dancing. Therefore, the “utility calculation” is that the net happiness of Mary and her three children will be higher if she stays home, even though Mary’s individual happiness might be slightly lower than it would have been if she had chosen to go dancing. Utility is often described in terms of pleasure, which can be problematic for utilitarianism. Imagine someone finds pleasure in playing video games and drinking beer all day long. Given a choice between, say, helping out in a homeless shelter or drinking and playing the newest video game, a person may well choose the latter, which suggests to some that utilitarianism has no way to distinguish between different kinds of pleasures. Presumably, we want our theory to be able to make a distinction between hedonistic and nobler pleasures. Mill saw this as a potential problem and insisted that pleasure should be considered not just in terms of quantity but also quality: that certain kinds of pleasures, or certain ways of satisfying desires, are simply better than others. A pig may be happy rolling around in the mud and eating garbage, but Mill insisted that people who take that approach to pleasure fail to develop their potential as human beings (relative to pigs, at least). According to Mill, it is better to be a dissatisfied Socrates than a satisfied pig. This is not to say that one should always choose something less pleasurable; rather, it is simply an indication that pleasures themselves can, or perhaps should, be distinguished from each other. It is not always easy to say that one pleasure is “superior” to another, and certainly people have long argued about this issue. However, these kinds of examples indicate a problem utilitarianism confronts if we evaluate acts solely in terms of their pleasurable consequences (Mill, 1909). mos81165_06_c06.indd 177 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Many people find utilitarianism to be an easy and useful approach to making ethical decisions. When distributing goods, services, or even time, it would seem to be a “no-brainer” to choose the option that would satisfy or please as many people as possible, compared to any other available choice. However, philosophers have raised a number of problems in response to utilitarianism, which may make it a less plausible ethical theory than it first appears. Problems With Utilitarianism Utilitarianism has what philosophers call an intuitive appeal: It seems to be relatively obvious, and just plain common sense, to evaluate our actions based on the results those actions produce. If all we know about a situation is that four kids in a sandbox have one toy, the best option would be for the children to share that toy, even if each child is quite sure he or she would get the most pleasure from playing with it alone. However, many philosophers have objected to utilitarianism, and for a number of reasons. As we have seen, distinguishing different kinds of pleasures from each other can be difficult. Does utilitarianism have any way to address the situation of a person who gets pleasure from staring at the wall or doing something else that most people would find quite unpleasant (something often called masochism)? Mill (1863) suggests there are “higher” or “more refined” pleasures and that they should be preferred, but who is to say which is a “higher” pleasure? Is reading poetry somehow better than watching soap operas? What if someone gains pleasure by sleeping all the time or hitting his thumb over and over with a hammer? More significant objections to utilitarianism have been posed on the basis of calculating the outcome, or consequences, of a choice. Suppose you are on a cruise ship that catches fire; you and 19 others are lucky enough to survive on a lifeboat. There is enough water to last for a week or more, but you have no food and do not know whether you will be rescued. Everyone is aware of how grim the future looks; as the boat drifts, everyone gets hungrier. It becomes apparent that everyone is going to die unless your group finds food. The utilitarian in the group poses the following options: All 20 people die, or 19 people live if one person is killed and eaten! To justify his position, he cites historical examples of similar cases in which cannibalism helped the majority survive. However, while this scenario may appear to result in the greatest good for the greatest number, do we really want an ethical theory that not only allows cannibalism, but actually endorses it as the fairest and most ethical decision? Few of us are likely to experience a situation this extreme, but we may find ourselves in situations where the basic utilitarian calculation actually leads to results that are very unfair and unjust. This is particularly threatening anytime individuals find themselves in a minority, whether because of their sex, race, ethnicity, religion, sexual orientation, or any of the other ways in which society categorizes people. For example, suppose a local grade school must decide if it should use taxpayer money to build ramps to make the building accessible to students in wheelchairs. This tax will likely decrease the pleasure of each taxpayer and may only be used by a few individuals throughout the year. In this way it would result in a net utility that would favor a decision not to build the ramps. Would you consider this a fair outcome? mos81165_06_c06.indd 178 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Great Ideas: The Trolley Problem A very famous challenge to our ethical intuitions, originated by Philippa Foot, is easy to describe but more problematic to solve. In Foot’s 1967 essay “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect,” she posed the following scenario known as the trolley problem: Imagine a runaway trolley hurtling toward five workers on the track. The driver must choose between staying the course, which would result in the death of the five workers, or divert the trolley to a spur where just one worker on the track would be killed. Most would say that diverting the trolley to save five lives while killing only one would be the better of the two options. Now imagine a similar scenario: What if a doctor could save the lives of five people who needed organ donations by killing one patient and distributing his organs? Would that be considered a moral act? If not, why would it be moral to kill the one track worker, but not the one patient? There are many variations on this basic scenario, which has generated a great deal of debate and discussion. Reflection Questions: With this in mind, consider the following questions: 1. Try to posit a situation where it would seem moral to kill (or allow to die) one person in order to save five people’s lives. 2. What is the relevant moral difference—if there is one—between killing someone and allowing someone to die? 3. Does it make a difference if one could save twenty people by sacrificing one person’s life? One hundred? One thousand? At what point might our views change due to the relationship between the one person sacrificed and the number of people saved? Tyranny of the Majority Dating as far back as Plato, political philosophers have often cited the tyranny of the majority, which is when the interests of the majority are placed above the interests of the minority, and to their detriment. American history is littered with such stories, whether the minority groups be African Americans, Native Americans, Jews, homosexuals, or many others. In the original, Protestant-dominated colonies, for example, Roman Catholics were not allowed to vote or hold public office. Despite the obvious injustice, this would seem to fit the utilitarian calculation, because Catholics were a minority at that time. This kind of calculation has been used to justify a wide range of policies that seem wrong, from slavery to refusing to sell houses in certain neighborhoods to ethnic and racial minorities. Interestingly, women have also suffered for similar reasons on the basis of this kind of calculation, despite the fact that they actually make up the majority of the population. Mill’s Response John Stuart Mill and other utilitarians recognized the flaws in an ethical system that had such unethical and oppressive results. One popular way of addressing these flaws has been to distinguish between act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism. Act utilitarianism simply involves a judgment of the act’s consequences: Given a set of choices, which act generates the greatest net good for the greatest number? Rule utilitarianism, on the other hand, involves an evaluation of the types of acts involved and proposes that, when followed as a general rule, the act should produce the greatest net good, or the greatest amount of happiness, for the greatest number. mos81165_06_c06.indd 179 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Consider the following example: Bob is taking an important physics test that he needs to pass to get into medical school. He considers the possibility that if he cheats “successfully,” he gains a great deal and thus achieves his greatest happiness, or “maximizes his utility” (we will ignore any feelings of guilt Bob may have). The act utilitarian would suggest that, in this case, cheating produces the greatest amount of good. The rule utilitarian would offer a different analysis. Bob may gain the most by cheating, but in general, we could not promote the rule that one should cheat. If we endorse a rule that says it is okay to cheat to get into medical school, then the rest of society would be considerably less confident that physicians were trustworthy and deserved their credentials. This would fail to generate the greatest good for the greatest number; therefore, the rule utilitarian would tell Bob not to cheat. Rule utilitarianism seems to have a better chance of dealing with some of the more obvious objections we have seen, although it is not entirely clear whether it can successfully treat the problem of a minority being oppressed by a majority. Mill (1909) seemed to advocate a system of “proportionate representation,” so minorities would be at least represented, but it is not clear how this solves the problem. Other objections have also been raised against both act and rule utilitarianism. For instance, when measuring pleasure, or utility, what time frame should be used: days, years, decades? Who is included in the idea of the “greatest number”—our family, our community, our country, our planet? How can one compare one person’s amount of pleasure with another person’s? Can we really even measure pleasure, or happiness, or utility in a way that allows us to make these utilitarian calculations? These are difficult questions to answer, and many philosophers have seen this as a reason to look elsewhere for a moral theory, one that does not evaluate acts in terms of consequences and does not measure such things as happiness and utility. The most famous alternative to utilitarianism is deontology, which is a nonconsequentialist theory. Deontology Deontological ethics is usually associated with the philosopher Immanuel Kant. Deontology comes from the Greek word for “obligation” (or “duty”). In contrast to consequentialist theories, Kant, and more generally the deontologist, ignores an act’s consequences when evaluating whether it is a good, bad, or morally neutral act. It is important to remember that deontologists do not deny that acts have consequences; their point is that those consequences should not play a role in evaluating the act’s morality. Rather, deontological ethics focuses on the will of the person acting, the person’s intention in carrying out the act, and particularly, the rule according to which the act is carried out. Deontology focuses on the duties and obligations one has in carrying out actions rather than on the consequences of those actions. In his Critique of Practical Reason, Kant (1997) claimed that certain kinds of rules established what he called a categorical imperative. This is a requirement or demand (imperative), and it has no exceptions (it is categorical). We might contrast this kind of imperative with what Kant calls a hypothetical imperative, which is illustrated by supposing you are hungry and decide to eat something; in this case the action (eating) is designed to achieve a goal (making you less hungry). Yet there is no obligation or demand that you eat; it is just what you do in this specific situation. Similarly, if you want to pass a course, a hypothetical imperative might tell you to study. In short, if someone adopts a certain goal, then actions that help achieve that goal are to be adopted. The categorical imperative, on the other hand, has no exceptions and is something one must do. As part of the categorical imperative, Kant assumes that being a moral person is a requirement; it is not merely a goal people may choose to strive for. mos81165_06_c06.indd 180 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 Kant offers several versions of the categorical imperative. We will look at the first two, which will give us a rough idea of what kind of rule it is. 1. Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time want that it should become a universal law. That is, if you choose to do something, would you desire that everyone in that same circumstance do exactly the same thing? 2. Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end and never merely as a means to an end. In other words, all people—including you—deserve respect. It would always be wrong to treat people as objects, or as a way of achieving some goal, or in another way that does not show respect. (Kant 1997, 1998) These rules may sound similar to that very famous and old Golden Rule: “Do unto others as you would have them do unto you.” The Golden Rule can be found in many different civilizations, beginning with the ancient Egyptians and the ancient Greeks, as well as in many religions, including Buddhism, Christianity, Judaism, and Islam. Yet there is a crucial distinction that Kant notes between the Golden Rule and the categorical imperative. Kant insists that rational agents should act in such a way that the rule they adopt can be followed universally, or by all rational agents. Otherwise, someone who might enjoy pain (a masochist) or enjoys inflicting pain (a sadist) might well be following the Golden Rule by treating others as he or she would like to be treated. Read Immanuel Kant’s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. Despite the distinction, there are many circumstances in which the categorical imperative and the Golden Rule lead to similar results. You do not want to be treated by others as some kind of “thing,” so you yourself should not treat others that way. This last claim is essentially what Kant provides as the second version of the categorical imperative. As we have seen, a simple utilitarian calculation has an intuitive appeal in that it seems fairly obvious to evaluate an act in terms of whether it produces the greatest net good for the greatest number. An indication that universal rules of behavior have their own intuitive appeal is borne out by the number of parents who use such rules with their children. For example, suppose a mother observes her daughter not sharing a toy with several other children; she is likely to take her daughter aside and ask, “How would you like it if no one shared toys with you?” The daughter, of course, would not like it, and—the mother hopes—the little girl will begin to understand that if she does not like to be treated in a certain way, then she should not treat others in that way. This question—”How would you like it if others treated you that way?”—is probably something all of us have heard before and is indicative of how familiar we are with this version of deontological ethics. Despite their differences, utilitarianism and deontology often come to the same conclusion, but from alternate directions. In the example of a group of children having one toy among them, the utilitarian would argue that the greatest net good for the greatest number is achieved by sharing the toy. The deontologist, on the other hand, would argue that people should treat others with the same respect they expect to be given, and that is best achieved by sharing the toy. They both conclude that the children should share, but one draws this conclusion by looking at the results, whereas the other draws the same conclusion by looking at the rule that should be followed. At the same time, other actions may generate conflicts between the two perspectives. For instance, a deontologist may adopt as the universal rule “Never steal.” Yet imagine a family that has no food; the deontologist may be forced to conclude that it would be wrong for the father to steal food to feed his mos81165_06_c06.indd 181 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 family. The utilitarian, in contrast, calculates that the unhappiness of the person from whom the food was stolen is not as great as the happiness achieved by the family getting food. Thus, the utilitarian may well argue that in this case stealing is not wrong because it produces the greatest good for the greatest number. Both utilitarianism and deontology have certain advantages. Utilitarian calculations are, at least at first glance, fairly easy to devise and provide a quick way to evaluate the moral worth of an act. Deontology, on the other hand, has the appeal of being easily explained and develops rules that seem to make sense and are also widely applied. We have already seen that utilitarianism confronts certain problems that expose how it may lead to results that appear unfair and unjust; we can now look at some similar kinds of problems that face the deontologist. Problems With Deontology Traditionally, critics of deontology have focused on two specific but related issues. First, deontology—particularly the Kantian version—seems too sterile and fails to capture some of the complex issues that arise when we confront ethical problems in real life. The second issue (which may be a result of the first) is that deontology may require one to act in a way that seems obviously wrong and unethical. As we saw with utilitarianism, any ethical theory that leads to potentially unethical results is problematic. We have seen the best known versions of Kant’s categorical imperative: That is, you should never treat others only as a means to achieve your goals, and you should only do something if everyone in that same situation would act the same way. The repeated use of the word should indicates these are normative demands, or moral claims. In some scenarios, the right course of action seems obvious. Just because you are late for a movie, you should not run over someone with your car on your way to the theater. No one in a similar situation should do so either. Following the Golden Rule would lead to the same result; after all, you would not want to be run over by someone rushing to get to the movies, so you should not run over someone to do so. Yet are there situations in which these kinds of rules result in actions that are wrong or even immoral? The most famous objection to the deontologist’s approach—specifically Kant’s—is the problem posed by lying. Lying is, of course, intentionally misleading someone to think something is true when it is false, or false when it is true. Children are taught at an early age never to lie, and most moral systems prohibit or at least discourage lying. Often, the Ninth Commandment given in the book of Exodus, “Thou shalt not bear false witness against thy neighbour” (Exodus 20:16), is interpreted to mean that lying is always wrong. Lying also seems to be a clear example of the categorical imperative: To lie to someone is to treat them with insufficient respect as a human being, and since we presumably do not want to be lied to, we should not lie to others. Still, people lie to each other quite a lot, and often to achieve goals that seem to be appropriate and moral (or at least not immoral). Consider the following four examples: 1. A husband buys a new shirt that he likes very much and asks his wife if it makes him look fat. In truth, the shirt does make him look fat. Should the wife tell her husband the truth? (The wife might avoid lying by not answering, but this may itself indicate her opinion.) 2. Dan and his friends are throwing an elaborate surprise party for Jody. Jody gets suspicious and asks Dan, “Are you throwing me a surprise party?” If Dan tells the truth, the mos81165_06_c06.indd 182 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 surprise party is ruined, and all their efforts will have been wasted. Should Dan lie to Jody? 3. Parents in the United States often tell their children made-up stories, not just about a jolly fat man who brings them presents at Christmastime, but also about a rabbit that brings candy at Easter and even a fairy who “buys” the teeth they have lost. Should parents always tell their children the truth about Santa Claus, the Easter bunny, and the tooth fairy? 4. Sarah comes to your door and asks you to hide her from an ax-wielding stalker. You agree without hesitation. Shortly thereafter, a wild-eyed man, holding an ax, asks you if you have hidden Sarah. Do you tell him the truth? (It is important to note that you are not being threatened; the man holding the ax asks about Sarah in a very polite and respectful manner.) We started with what seemed to be a good, widely accepted rule: “Never lie.” Yet the preceding examples illustrate the complexity of applying this rule. Do the people who lie in the above examples act immorally? The wife does not want to make her husband feel bad; Dan wants to make sure Jody enjoys her surprise; parents want their children to be captivated by Santa Claus and provide incentive for good behavior; and lying to an ax-wielding stalker might save Sarah’s life. Kant’s stern rule about never lying, then, seems to force everyone in the above cases to do something they would prefer not to do. Perhaps the husband, Jody, the children, and the stalker would prefer to be lied to? One might tinker with Kant’s rule, or suggest that one should not ask questions unless one expects to be told the truth. One might also say that children are special cases and have not reached the age where we are always honest with them. Yet this logic results in a rule that is even more convoluted: “Never lie,” morphs into something like, “Never lie to those over a certain age, and hope no one asks you questions they really would prefer not be answered truthfully.” Even this variation on the rule may be problematic; we can probably think of examples where lying seems to be the right thing to do. Formulating a rule that allows for those examples is a difficult task. We have seen the advantages of utilitarianism and deontology, as well as some of their problems. One other classical, or traditional, theory remains; it does not look at the consequences of our acts (as in utilitarianism, or consequentialism) or at the acts themselves and the rules that guide those acts (as in deontology, or nonconsequentialism). Rather, it looks at the character of the person acting. This is a theory known as virtue ethics. Virtue Ethics Virtue ethics is an approach to moral and ethical questions that focuses on a person’s character. Some discussion of this concept can be found in the writings of Plato, as well as in the teachings of Chinese philosophers such as Confucius (551–479 bce). However, the classic conception of virtue ethics in Western philosophy is attributed to Aristotle. For Aristotle, the virtuous person, or the person of virtuous character, is someone who has admirable characteristics and displays them in a way that is balanced and harmonious. This person seeks to have an ideal character, and the virtues that contribute to this goal will all be appropriately related to each other. Ultimately, the person with practical or moral wisdom—what Aristotle calls phronesis—will have the appropriate virtues, will know how to use them, and will possess moral excellence. Such a person will achieve the specific kind of happiness Aristotle describes as human flourishing. mos81165_06_c06.indd 183 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? Read more about virtue ethics in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. CHAPTER 6 Some of these virtues are traditional characteristics that we still use to describe a good, moral, or virtuous person, including courage, generosity, and being a good friend. According to Aristotle, a person may have too little courage, which we would call cowardice. Another person may have too much courage, resulting in rash behavior. A soldier who runs from the field of battle when first confronting the enemy might not have enough courage, whereas the soldier who runs straight into machine-gun fire may have too much. Aristotle insists that the virtuous person will have the right amount of courage and will aim at what he calls the golden mean between having too little and having too much of a given characteristic. Thus, someone who displays little generosity will fall on one end of the spectrum (miserly); someone who is much too generous will fall on the opposite end (wasteful); and a moderately generous person falls in the middle and is virtuous. The person who has the requisite moral wisdom, or phronesis, will know how to act in a given situation, and those acts will be in harmony with the other virtues that make up this person’s character. Aristotle also describes two virtues that are a bit more complex. One of these he calls temperance, or sophrosunë (Aristotle, 2002). A temperate person is moderate and has self-control. This person is able to control his or her emotions through reason and does not indulge in the extreme. When it comes to drinking wine, the intemperate person will drink too much of it, whereas the person who rejects it entirely, in spite of finding it enjoyable, is regarded as insensible. Temperance, then, is a middle ground between the two excesses of insensibility and intemperance. Aristotle also describes a virtue he calls magnanimity, which is how we see ourselves and how we are regarded by others (Aristotle, 2002). This can involve the respect others give us and also the kinds of rewards and honors we can receive. Along with justice, Aristotle considered this to be the highest virtue. Magnanimity is translated from the Greek word megalopsuchia, which literally means “great soul” or “great mind.” This is a person who represents excellence, is worthy of being honored by others, and knows that he or she is worthy. Neither arrogant nor falsely modest, the virtuous person demonstrates magnanimity, and as a virtue, it is possessed in a reasonable amount. People who think too highly of themselves or who think they deserve more recognition than they actually do are considered vain. On the other hand, those who believe they deserve no recognition or appreciation when the opposite is likely true have too little magnanimity, a characteristic Aristotle calls “low-minded.” We might call such a person too self-effacing, or falsely modest. The truly magnanimous person has this virtue in its proper proportion; such a person will be appropriately modest while appropriately proud of his or her accomplishments. To see how virtues might interact with and balance against one another, consider the following example. Suppose Nick likes to go to parties, but he drinks too much and acts as if he is everyone’s best friend. One night a fight breaks out, and Nick tries to stop it by fighting with everyone involved in the original fight. Nick is unable to keep his desires in check by practical reason; does not live in accordance with the golden mean, and he indulges in excess. In contrast, Ted never goes to parties; he stays home alone and never has any fun. Once, when he saw someone steal an elderly woman’s purse, he ran in the opposite direction. Ted also does not have his desires by reason, does not live in accordance with the golden mean, and disproportionately deprives himself. Neither Nick nor Ted would qualify as having a virtuous character. Jennifer, on the other hand, is a good friend; she is courageous; she is modest but takes pride in what she does and accepts the legitimate praise of others; and she is generous, honest, and moderate. She has what the Greeks called mos81165_06_c06.indd 184 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.1 How Should One Act? CHAPTER 6 eudaimonia, which can be translated in a variety of ways, including happiness, flourishing, and well-being. Aristotle would say that because Jennifer’s virtues are in their proper balance and proportion, she has eudaimonia. It is easy to get lost in Aristotle’s technical vocabulary, but his basic point is that the person who makes the right moral choices, or behaves ethically, is a virtuous person and is the kind of person we admire for that reason. We object to those who are deficient in one or more of the characteristics we have mentioned, but we also object to those who display one or more of these attributes excessively. The person who has eudaimonia is the person who has acquired the correct conception of the virtues, individually and as a whole, and as such, offers us an example of what kinds of moral choices should be made. We may not actually know of such a person, and indeed such a person may not actually exist. However, the conception of such a virtuous person helps us examine our own choices and behavior to see where we are doing the right thing and where we may need improvement. As is often the case with ethical theories, virtue ethics initially sounds clear, obvious, and easy to apply. But just as challenges exist to both utilitarianism and deontology, certain problems arise for proponents of virtue ethics. Problems With Virtue Ethics Virtue ethics differs from utilitarianism and deontology in that it examines not what a person does, but what kind of character he or she has. In addition to the virtues, this theory provides us with a spectrum on which to moderate our own behavior, as well as an ideal for which to strive. Applying these notions in real-world examples is more difficult than it would initially appear, however. For example, consider one of Aristotle’s specific virtues, courage. While it is easy to imagine plenty of scenarios in which someone has an excess of courage or a lack of sufficient courage, it is difficult to determine what the appropriate amount of courage would be for more nuanced situations. Imagine Steve is a prisoner of war, kept in very brutal conditions with a number of his fellow soldiers. He knows he has a fairly good chance of escaping, but if he is caught, the guards will torture and execute him. He also knows that if a prisoner successfully escapes, the guards will choose another prisoner at random, torture him, and then execute him. To escape under these conditions requires a certain degree of courage; but choosing not to escape also requires some courage. Under these circumstances, how should Steve be appropriately courageous? It is not clear that there is a golden mean to which Steve can appeal, and it is therefore not clear which, if either, of the possible actions is virtuous. In this specific case then, it seems that virtue ethics lacks sufficient guidance for how to act. Similar problems confront the other virtues. Is there an “appropriate amount” of lying one should do in order to be virtuous? Should one be willing to break some promises but keep others? Even if we think there may be solutions to various individual ethical dilemmas, virtue ethics seems to fail to offer the kind of general solution offered by utilitarianism and deontology. Another problem with virtue ethics is that Aristotle and many virtue ethicists seem to think that certain terms are well understood and that everyone shares the same general conception of the virtues. But do we? We may think that friendship, for example, is universally understood. Yet imagine Carl, who thinks of himself as a very good friend to Charles and Kate, the couple that lives next door. Carl discovers that Charles has been having an affair with Kate’s best friend. Presumably, friends tell each other the truth, but friends also do not want to see their friends hurt, mos81165_06_c06.indd 185 1/6/14 2:33 PM CHAPTER 6 Section 6.1 How Should One Act? Read Alasdair MacIntyre’s work After Virtue in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. their marriages broken, and so on. It is not at all clear what Carl should do in this case. More importantly, people would likely disagree over what Carl should do if he is actually to be a good friend. Thus, we all may not share the same general conception of “friendship.” Such problems multiply because each virtue will confront this kind of problem and will encounter further problems upon trying to determine the appropriate amount of each virtue and how they should be balanced with each other. It is for this reason that some philosophers have rejected virtue ethics entirely. For example, in his text After Virtue, Alasdair MacIntyre (2007) dismisses the concept and possibly even the existence of virtues. One other traditional problem for virtue ethics is that of relativity, or when one culture views an act as a virtue but another regards that very same act as a vice. Consider two communities, A and Z. A is a culture of warriors that insists its members be fierce and respond violently to threats. Z is a culture of pacifists that insists its members always “turn the other cheek” and respond to threats with nonviolence and negotiation. A group of outsiders, X, sets up camp outside of both A’s and Z’s land. X appears to have a great number of weapons and may well pose a threat. Accordingly, A reacts to X’s presence violently, while Z reacts to X’s presence nonviolently. Virtue ethics does not seem to offer a wholly adequate way of determining whether A’s violent response or Z’s nonviolent response is appropriate. A will regard Z’s pacifism as immoral, just as Z will regard A’s violence as immoral. The point is not so much to determine whether A or Z (or neither) is doing the virtuous thing. Rather, it is that virtue ethics does not seem to offer enough guidance to make this determination. Or it ends up saying that both responses, for the respective culture, are virtuous. But if all our moral evaluations must be made relative to a given culture, then virtue ethics cannot address actions that have different value in different cultures. In other words, if evaluations are relativized, then virtue ethics does nothing more than say some things are right and some are wrong, but no one can really object when someone from another culture does something wrong so long as they act within their culture’s moral parameters. There are those who do indeed support this view, which is known as ethical relativism. (See Table 6.1 for a review of ethical theories and theorists.) Table 6.1: Concept review: Theories and theorists mos81165_06_c06.indd 186 Ethical theory Key figure Basic idea Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill An act (or rule) is good or right if it produces the greatest net good for the greatest number. Deontology Immanuel Kant An act is good or right if it is done because it is the right thing to do, in accordance with a justified moral rule or rules. Virtue ethics Aristotle Morality is determined on the basis of specific virtues, exemplified by a person of noble or virtuous character. 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 Great Ideas: Different Cultures, Different Ethics? In ancient China emperors were known to have several wives. They also had dozens, even thousands, of concubines, women who functioned as “secondary wives” in many ways, including sexually. For example, Emperor Taizong (599–649) of the Tang Dynasty was reputed to have 3,000 concubines. With this in mind, consider the following questions: 1. 2. 3. 4. How might a utilitarian argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally? How might a deontologist argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally? How might a virtue ethicist argue that Emperor Taizong was acting immorally? Is there an argument that justifies Emperor Taizong’s behavior? What would such an argument look like? 5. Do you think ethical values change over time? Would this affect how we might judge this situation today, and how we might have judged this situation in the 7th century? 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics E ach of the three classic ethical theories—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics—has advantages and disadvantages, and none offers an obvious or easily applied solution to the question, “What should I do?” In this section, we will look at alternatives that have been developed in contrast to these three classic theories. Technically, these are regarded as “metaethical” views, in contrast to normative ethics. Normative ethics provides a way of evaluating acts as moral or determining whether a given act is right or wrong. Metaethics, as employed here, is the attempt to understand what ethics is and how we can and should understand moral questions and evaluations. Ethical Egoism Ego comes from the Greek word for “I.” Most readers probably know at least a few people who could be described as having a big ego; that is, people with an exaggerated sense of their abilities, talents, accomplishments, or qualities. Egoism, then, means to have a focus on one’s self, and ethical egoism is the idea that one’s conception of right and wrong, good and evil, and other moral terms are determined by one’s own sense of value. To return to the notion of utility, we could describe this position as advocating that one should do what maximizes one’s own utility. In short, I should do what is in my own self-interest. Thus, in the most literal sense, this theory is selfish. Yet unlike more traditional moral theories, selfishness, or self-interest, is not seen as wrong or immoral, but the preferred way for one to act. Let us return to the example of the group of children playing in a sandbox with access to only one toy. Sally, the ethical egoist—who we will just call the egoist from now on—determines that what makes her happiest, or maximizes her utility, is to have the toy to herself. Thus, it is in Sally’s self-interest to get the toy, keep the toy, and play with they toy all by herself. This is not, however, the only result possible. It may be that she decides that she would get more out of it if everyone shared, or for that matter, if only one other person got to play with the toy. If she concludes that some other option is in her self-interest, then she should adopt that choice. So we can see that the crucial factor in this case is not that Sally gets the toy to herself; it is that what she perceives as most beneficial to herself will be what she should do. mos81165_06_c06.indd 187 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics Read Joel Feinberg’s “Psychological Egoism” in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. CHAPTER 6 Now let us revisit the example of Mary, who is trying to decide whether to go dancing or stay home with her three children. Factoring in the happiness of Mary and the three children, the utilitarian argued that everyone would be best off if Mary stayed home—that this scenario would produce the greatest net good for the greatest number. The egoist might conclude otherwise: If Mary sees her greatest happiness achieved by going out dancing, then she should go out dancing. Again, Mary may conclude that it would make her happiest to stay home. The egoist’s position is that what Mary should do is whatever Mary sees as in her self-interest. We saw that the classic theories of ethics—utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics— all had problems when we tried to apply them to real life. Egoism, however, seems not to have that problem. People determine what is in their self-interest. They do what they think will make them best off, and according to this theory, that is what they should do. Suppose Joe is a retired billionaire investment banker. He has several houses, cars, and servants and can take vacations whenever and wherever he wants. One day Joe sees Mike, an old friend from high school who has become homeless. Mike asks Joe for $10. For Joe, this amount is almost nothing; but Joe considers whether he would be better off giving the money to Mike or keeping it himself. Joe decides he would be happier keeping his money; egoism tells us that is what he should do. Traditional ethical theories and religious views may regard Joe as being selfish, greedy, and more generally, acting immorally. Egoism, however, does not; traditional conceptions of selfishness are not regarded by egoism as immoral. It may turn out, of course, that Joe decides that it is in his self-interest to give Mike the $10; it might make him feel better to help out an old friend, and after all, it is not much of a sacrifice for Joe. But egoism leaves that decision up to Joe, and what Joe perceives to be in his own self-interest is what Joe should do. Many economists have argued that this is in fact how economic exchanges work in free markets. Buyers want to get as much as they can as cheaply as they can; sellers want to sell as much as they can for the highest price. Individuals, then, want to maximize their utility by getting as much as they can out of the exchange. In the traditional views, this sounds not just selfish, but greedy. Yet we assume everyone has, more or less, the same amount of information about the product involved, and we also assume that everyone knows that everyone else is trying to maximize his or her self-interest. In this way the market will in theory be most efficient and create more goods and more wealth for everyone if everyone acts in ways that maximize his or her self-interest. Recognizing that greed was traditionally regarded as sin, political economist Bernard Mandeville (1670–1733) claimed that great benefits would be produced if everyone were greedy. He described this arrangement as “private vices, public benefits”: That is, the private vice of selfishness would actually end up making society wealthier than it would have been otherwise, which is a public benefit. Joel Feinberg (1926–2004) is another philosopher who considered the role of selfishness in human actions. Feinberg, however, argues against psychological egoism, the idea that humans are internally driven to do all acts by selfish motives. He demonstrates logical inconsistencies in this position and ultimately claims that it is an unsound judgment about human motives in ethical judgment. Problems With Ethical Egoism Ethicists, religious leaders, and many others protest against ethical egoism because it seems to promote selfishness. The objection is fairly obvious: Being selfish is wrong, either mos81165_06_c06.indd 188 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 because it is immoral, a sin, or both; so too must be an ethical theory that promotes it. However, another more subtle question might trouble the ethical egoist: How do we determine our self-interest? Ethical egoism assumes that any individual can identify what is in his or her self-interest, but that may not always be the case. When considering what action to take, do I evaluate my selfinterest in the short term, the long term, or something in between? Perhaps I think it is in my short-term self-interest to eat an entire blueberry pie because it is delicious; this will be against my self-interest, however, if I have a long-term goal of losing weight. Perhaps we could adopt the principle that my long-term interest should always override my short-term interest. Yet can I really be sure what my long-term interest is and that it will not change? Even if the question of what I know about my self-interest can be answered, a bigger problem may then arise: Can I ever be wrong about my self-interest? If whatever I do is defined as having been done in my selfinterest, then how could I ever do something against my self-interest? The egoist maxim “One should do whatever one does” does not seem to offer much in the way of guidance. An example further illustrates this. Suppose Emma decides it is in her self-interest to become, over time, very wealthy. Despite her love of shopping, taking nice vacations, and going out to expensive dinners with her friends, she resists doing so and becomes very frugal. She only buys the cheapest things and has to actively resist her friends’ invitations to do all her favorite activities. She puts all the money she saves into the stock market and other investments and slowly starts to generate a substantial amount of money. She sees her friends less and less often and becomes somewhat of a hermit. After several years she realizes that she is very lonely, does not have much fun, and is generally unpleasant to be around. Even though she has met her goal of becoming wealthy, she realizes that she sacrificed too much to reach that goal. She decides to give all of her money away to charity and focuses on doing volunteer work to help others. The ethical egoist would have offered Emma little guidance. By choosing her long-term goals over her short-term goals, Emma presumably maximized her utility. However, had she decided otherwise—to continue shopping, vacationing, and eating at expensive restaurants—she would have maximized her utility as well. This is because she would have made either choice in her own self-interest. Worse yet, her long-term goals changed, so she gave up not just her short-term pleasures but also her original long-term goal when she adopted a new one. Whatever Emma determines is in her self-interest is what she should do, but she clearly was not able to determine what that long-term self-interest really was. Great Ideas: Short-Term and Long-Term Interests Mark graduated from college six months ago. He has $5,000 in student loans and $1,000 in savings. He has been looking for a job for several weeks, with no luck. Reflection Questions: With this in mind, consider the following questions: 1. Which of the following should Mark pursue if he wants to maximize his short-term interests? 2. Which of the following should Mark pursue if he wants to maximize his long-term interests? (continued) mos81165_06_c06.indd 189 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 Great Ideas: Short-Term and Long-Term Interests (continued) 3. How confident should Mark be about these decisions? In other words, can he distinguish with a very high degree of certainty between his short-term and long-term interests? A. Mark borrows more money to buy an expensive guitar he has wanted for several years, in order to become a professional musician. B. Mark invests $500 and pays $500 on his student loans. C. Mark pays $1,000 on his student loans. D. Mark invests $1,000 in a speculative stock offering, having been told by a friend that the stock will go up 100% in the next year. E. Mark buys $1,000 in lottery tickets. Like utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics, ethical egoism also falls short on the ethical issue of lying. The classical theories all had guidance for when or if one should lie, but their results were unsatisfactory and occasionally led to strange or even wrong outcomes. An egoist would be even less helpful on this subject. If Carolyn asks Bob to go to the movies but Bob does not want to go, should he lie and say he is busy? Should he tell the truth and say he does not want to go? The advice ethical egoism seems to offer is that it is all right for him to lie if he does so out of self-interest; the same is true if he tells the truth out of self-interest. It is unclear how this reasoning can help Bob make an ethical decision, however. Relativism We have now examined a number of theories and also acknowledged that each has its problems. One might be tempted to abandon the search for an ethical theory at this point, at least one that tells people what they should do and how they should live. Rather than taking this course of action, however, we should recognize that there are no universal or general ethical standards; that a person’s ethical view is relative to his or her culture, society, tradition, religion, worldview, and even individual values. Because moral claims are said to be relative to something else, this is a metaethical view known as relativism. Even though philosophers distinguish between different kinds of relativism, we will generally use the term to mean that any ethical claim is relative to a set of beliefs and that any such ethical claim is true, or consistent with, that set of beliefs. To take a simple example: Suppose you like comedies and your best friend likes action films. It is not too problematic here to reject the suggestion that comedies are better than action films or to reject the suggestion that action films are better than comedies; each claim is relative to one’s beliefs, desires, and preferences. Although it may make things more difficult when you and your friend go see a movie together, neither of you is determined to convince the other that there is some true, objective, or factual claim being ignored about the merits of comedies and action films. Moral Relativism Moral relativism extends this idea to the area of ethics. Ethical evaluations—saying some act is right or wrong—are made in terms of the context of that act and therefore are relative to the actor’s culture and values. For example, some cultures bury their dead; some cremate their dead; some allow them to be exposed to the elements and scavengers; some mummify their dead (at least their important dead, such as Egyptian pharaohs); some cultures have even been reported to eat their dead. Which is right? Are any of these wrong? Some religions require the cremation of the dead, whereas other religions prohibit it. What is the relativist response to these issues? mos81165_06_c06.indd 190 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 The relativist simply says that the practice a given culture adopts as correct determines what should be done. Let culture A be a society that cremates, or ritually burns, its dead, while culture B is a society that prohibits cremation. The relativist says A’s tradition is correct for A and not for B; in the same way, B’s tradition is correct for B and not for A. Just as important for the view we are calling moral relativism is that those who live in culture A cannot say that cremating is right and not cremating is wrong; they can only say it is right for them. In the same way, those in culture B cannot say that cremating is wrong and not cremating is right; they can only say it is wrong for them. The opinion of cremation, then, is relative to the given culture, and there is no objective ethical standard to appeal to for determining whether cremating one’s dead is right or wrong. Many people find this position very attractive. It seems to eliminate the need, or desire, to provide objective evaluations for all people and all societies. It allow us to simply “agree to disagree,” in that if some culture or society or religion does something that our society would deem as immoral, we are free to say it is wrong for our society but not for others. Moral relativism is often characterized in terms of cultures, and cultural anthropologists have identified many practices that contrast, and even conflict, with some of the standard Western traditions. There are numerous rituals and ceremonies relating to birth, achieving adult status, marrying, and dying, to name a few, that reflect a wide range of beliefs and values. We saw that Aristotle recommended generosity, within its appropriate limits, as one of the chief qualities a virtuous person would possess. Imagine a society in which people who are deemed good or virtuous are those who have the greatest wealth; in this society people would gain virtuous status by accumulating as much as they can and keeping it all to themselves. In contrast, consider a society in which people are deemed good or virtuous if they give all of their wealth away. Aristotle regarded a moderate amount of generosity as universally virtuous. Here we see that the moral relativist might regard a deficiency of generosity (keeping everything for oneself) as a virtue, relative to a society’s values; an excess of generosity (giving everything away) can also be seen as virtue, relative to a society’s values. The moral relativist concludes that the claim “generosity is a virtue” can only be evaluated in terms of a specific society’s values. Great Ideas: Cultural Relativism Consider some of the following activities that involve cultural practices and traditions. Can you imagine a version of one or more of these practices that you would find objectionable? What does cultural relativism tell us about your objection? If you cannot imagine any practice that is objectionable, does that mean absolutely everything is morally permissible? If so, what are the implications of this idea? • • • • • • • • • • mos81165_06_c06.indd 191 Dating Marriage Health care How the elderly are treated What foods one can eat Raising children Education Encountering strangers Death Adultery 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 Just as we considered the perspective of the other moral theories on this subject, what would the moral relativist have to say on the topic of lying? Is it wrong to lie? Is it okay to lie? Is it sometimes wrong to lie and sometimes right to lie? The moral relativist would likely say, “It depends.” If your society rewards lying, or at least does not punish it, then lying might well be okay. If your society, on the other hand, has strict penalties against lying (whether legal, official, or informally enforced by community members), then lying will be wrong. “Lying is right” or “lying is wrong” are the kinds of claims avoided by the moral relativist, who would advocate statements more along the lines of, “Lying is right relative to a society that permits or encourages lying” and “Lying is wrong relative to a society that prohibits lying.” Extreme Relativism So far we have discussed relativism in terms of societies and cultures. However, it is worth pointing out there is an extreme, or radical, kind of relativism, often associated with the ancient Greek philosopher Protagoras (ca. 490–420 bce). This kind of relativism is said to hold true for individuals: If a person says something is true or false, right or wrong, then it is true or false and right or wrong for that person. We saw an example of this when you and your friend discussed your preferences for movies: For you it was true that comedies were best; for your friend, it was true that action films were best. Protagorean, or extreme, relativism extends this idea to all claims, including ethical ones. Presumably, this means if you think shoplifting is wrong but another person says shoplifting is not wrong, there is no “fact” we can point to in order to determine who is correct. Shoplifting is wrong for you, but not wrong (or even right) for the other person. That is about all there is to say about such disagreements. This kind of relativism is often attractive in ethics because it allows us to avoid judging or criticizing other people and cultures. This is especially true when we are considering cultures and traditions with which we are not very familiar. However, similar to the other moral theories, issues have been raised with relativism as well. Problems With Relativism One problem with relativism is that some acts or traditions seem wrong not just in relation to a culture, but simply wrong on their own. For example, an ancient Hindu practice called suttee requires a woman whose husband has recently died to commit suicide by throwing herself on his funeral pyre. This can be done voluntarily, or she might be forced to do so. (The practice has been outlawed but occasionally still occurs.) Some societies continue to practice slavery. Others make child pornography widely available. Some societies practice infanticide, or the killing (or allowing to die) of an infant after birth if it lacks desired characteristics (frequently if it is a girl). Some societies have executed prisoners—often on flimsy or inadequate charges and with little legal protection—in order to take their organs and sell them on the black market. Of course, the 20th century offered many examples of leaders—Joseph Stalin, Mao Tse-tung, and Adolf Hitler, to name a few—who caused the deaths of millions under their reign. The relativist would seem to say that such examples are wrong only relative to a specific culture or worldview. Perhaps we are from a culture that views infanticide or slavery as wrong; we would then say that, for us, these things are wrong. Yet from the perspective of a culture that does not share our views, perhaps infanticide or slavery—or both—are not wrong or are even right. The extreme cases tend to make people uncomfortable, which is the point. Do we want to say that a government policy that results in family members eating each other is only wrong relative to mos81165_06_c06.indd 192 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 a given value system, or that such a policy is simply, fundamentally, universally, and obviously wrong? To be consistent, the relativist has to say that no matter how wrong something seems to be, the idea of “wrong” is still relative. This suggestion may make you as uncomfortable as it makes some ethical theorists. Reformer’s Dilemma A second, more sophisticated objection to relativism, known as the “Reformer’s Dilemma” (Feldman, 1978, p. 166), has been provided by the philosopher Fred Feldman (b. 1941). Imagine Sarah lives in a society that values boys but not girls. To keep the society going, some number of girls is needed, but parents are allowed to kill a third, female child if they already have a girl. Furthermore, if a couple already has three children, girls or boys, they are required to kill all subsequent female children. Sarah thinks this is wrong; perhaps she just feels it is wrong, or perhaps she has substantial arguments for her position. Yet moral relativism says that her society determines what is wrong or right, and it has determined that killing girls is right. So Sarah must be wrong to object to this policy. More generally, anyone who objects to any of a society’s policies must be wrong. Thus, by this logic, Martin Luther King Jr. would have been wrong to object to oppressive and racist American practices in the 1960s; Nelson Mandela would have been wrong to object to the oppressive and racist South African system of apartheid. In fact, anyone who wished to change society could never be correct. This seems problematic, given that many of history’s most admired people were critical of their societies. Worse, this seems to suggest that if criticizing social values always puts a person in the wrong, then society cannot ever be improved, and thus must be perfect. Yet as Feldman observes, this poses a challenge to the absolute relativist. Remembering What We Agree On Perhaps the most sophisticated response to relativism can be found in the work of American philosopher Donald Davidson, who expanded upon the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Davidson (1974) argues that radical relativism is incoherent, for several reasons. First, assume that the relativist is right and that a person’s beliefs are relative to his or her society. However, we must recall that within any society, a person can “belong” to many different kinds of groups, based on ethnicity, class, income level, language, gender, race, religion, sexual orientation, and so on. Consider Jafari, who has lived for most of his life in France but was born in Egypt. His native language is Arabic and he is Muslim. From which group does he derive his values? What if one group to which Jafari belongs approves of, say, restricting women from working outside the home, whereas another group to which he belongs disapproves of such a prohibition? How does Jafari figure out whether it is right or wrong? To take the idea to its extreme, does a poor White 50-year-old Lutheran heterosexual woman from Texas have moral values in common with an 18-year-old wealthy Chinese lesbian or with a homosexual middle-class 50-year-old White Unitarian male from Pennsylvania? It seems that the many factors that constitute culture pose a problem for the relativist who argues that culture determines our values. Second, Davidson points out that when discussing ethical viewpoints, politics, religion, and other controversial topics, we almost always focus on the areas over which we disagree. Yet in order to reach a point of disagreement, there are actually numerous issues and ideas upon which we actually agree. Consider a debate over gun control between Jim and John. Jim thinks no one should be able to own a handgun; John thinks everyone should be required to own a handgun. Their disagreement seems substantial, yet imagine if they started their disagreement by listing mos81165_06_c06.indd 193 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 the points on which they agree, the points that make their disagreement possible—such as that guns do not speak Japanese, guns do not make good hats, guns are not an appropriate filling for sandwiches, guns cannot fly, and so on. This exercise hardly makes our disagreements disappear, yet it highlights how people’s agreements typically outnumber their disagreements. As Davidson puts it, disagreements—even between two people from dramatically different cultures—can only occur within the context of massive agreement, or on the assumption of an enormous background of shared ideas. Relativists would likely purport that two people from different cultures would agree on very little. However, in order to disagree, Davidson argues that they must agree on an awful lot even to reach the point of disagreement. Nietzsche’s Challenge Relativism seems to place ethical problems on a scale of “difficult to solve” to “unsolvable.” As Davidson indicates, this may be the consequence of focusing exclusively on what divides us rather than what unites us. Others have challenged even more fundamentally the values of society as a whole, including traditional political and religious structures. Perhaps the most powerful such challenge came from the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s father, uncle, and grandfathers were all Lutheran pastors, but Nietzsche’s father died when he was 4 years old, and his brother died a few months later. Nietzsche was raised by his mother and sister, was sent to a highly prestigious boarding school in Germany, and at the age of just 24 accepted a position to teach classical philology (the study of classical Greek and Latin texts) at the University of Basel in Switzerland. Nietzsche taught there for 10 years, but his job was interrupted by military service, during which he received a serious injury. His health in general was not good, and he had to resign from his teaching post. He spent much of the rest of his life wandering around Italy, France, Switzerland, and Germany. In 1889 Nietzsche had a mental breakdown and collapsed in Turin, Italy. He spent the remaining years of his life unable to communicate, not realizing that the many books he had produced had begun to make him a world-famous philosopher. Übermensch Nietzsche’s influence on 20th-century philosophy is difficult to overstate. He presented, and still represents, a radical challenge to traditional ethical viewpoints. His position called for a reevaluation of all values; that is, a criticism and scrutiny of all the various things that traditional morality and religion had said were good or wrong. In doing so Nietzsche determined that much of traditional morality was fundamentally wrong. He declared that “God is dead” (and had been killed by human beings) and defended atheism. Nietzsche thought that Judaism and Christianity had adopted the ancient ideas of the Greeks and Romans and perverted them. Before Christianity, the “good” was identified as the strong, the powerful, the courageous, the noble, and the creative; the “bad” was that which was weak, timid, small-minded, and cowardly. Nietzsche argued that Christianity turned this upside down. He suggested that people had been convinced by “the priests”—those who control a society’s moral, cultural, political, and religious values—that what had been good was now evil and what had been bad was now good. Hence, he saw the prevailing morality as preventing those who were noble, creative, and bold from being recognized as superior to the masses. He also argued that the masses—who were timid and weak—could be easily controlled by those in power, like sheep by a shepherd. He thought both Christianity and mos81165_06_c06.indd 194 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 democracy (a democracy being of a mass of people who were kept ignorant and did what they were told) held back society’s very few exceptional individuals who were capable of achieving greatness. Such an individual was called by Nietzsche an Übermensch, which is usually translated as “superman” or “overman” (Nietzsche, 1973). This overman creates his (or her; Nietzsche’s issues with women are notorious, but very complex) own values, and his own morality, as an expression of his power to overcome the values people around him have tried to force upon him. In this way the overman becomes a free and independent spirit, risking everything in his unwillingness to accept social conventions. Ultimately, Nietzsche (1974) suggests a view he calls “eternal recurrence” as the goal of the truly noble soul: People should seek a life that they would be happy living if they were to have to live exactly that way for eternity. Read Friedrich Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil in the Chapter Readings section of the Appendix. Critiques of Nietzsche Those who have resisted Nietzsche’s ideas (and there are many) do so for a number of reasons. Unlike Nietzsche, they think moral and religious traditions express important truths and values, and certainly disagree that “God is dead.” Most Nietzsche scholars reject the idea that he was the type of extreme relativist discussed previously in this chapter; however, it is easy to see why some might regard him that way. After all, if one creates one’s own values, then those values would seem relative to that person. Some critics regard Nietzsche as elitist because of his suggestion that just a few “great souls” were allowed full access to freedom and independence, but the great masses who did not so qualify were relegated to mediocrity, following rules they did not understand and more or less doing what they were told. Oronoz/SuperStock Friedrich Nietzsche called for intense scrutiny and criticism of all of what traditional morality and religion had deemed as good and bad. mos81165_06_c06.indd 195 However, there is no denying that in the history of ethics, Nietzsche presents a serious challenge to a number of different moral and religious traditions. He requires us to examine our moral values and see how we use them to justify our actions. Has Christianity been used to promise people a true reward that will come after death to make it easier to control them while alive? Have Western societies often punished people who are unwilling to go along with their overriding values? Interestingly enough, at times Nietzsche identified Jesus as a person whom society punished for being brave and independent enough to raise profound objections to the values imposed upon him, but Nietzsche (1968) also remarked that the “last true Christian died on the cross” (sec. 39). Have societies that officially or unofficially regarded themselves as Christian acted in ways that violate the very Christian principles they are said to embrace? These and many of Nietzsche’s other questions are important reminders that people often say one thing but do another. Nietzsche’s 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 willingness to expose this hypocrisy has continued to confront Western philosophy, specifically its development of moral theories. He has, therefore, demanded that philosophers and all those interested in moral questions carefully consider whether what we do actually conforms to what we believe. Demanding we make this critical and uncomfortable self-examination is the very thing that makes those demanding it unpopular; many think this was precisely the reason Socrates was executed. At the same time, most of us recognize that it is to our benefit to see if there are any contradictions between what we believe, why we believe it, and how we treat others. Tolerance and Diversity We may well reject Nietzsche’s scathing critique of society and its hypocrisy. We may also resist what seem to be Nietzsche’s elitism and his lack of tolerance. At the same time, given the increasing global interdependence and the diversity of societies, philosophers have also worried about whether we can determine what an appropriate amount of tolerance is. The United States is a diverse country, with people from a vast number of backgrounds who represent numerous ethnic groups, religious traditions, and countries of origin. Some 80% of Americans speak English, but according to the 2010 U.S. Census, more than 350 other languages are spoken (or signed) in the United States (although some of these are spoken by a very small groups). Some estimate there are more than 200 different religious denominations in the United States. There is even more diversity globally, of course: The planet’s 7 billion people speak thousands of different languages, practice thousands of different religious traditions and denominations, and are composed of thousands of different ethnic groups. In India alone, for example, some 350 different languages are spoken by a substantial number of people, even though its official state language is Hindi (and its secondary “official” language is English). Assuming that differences in culture, religion, ethnicity, and other value systems generate disagreement, this degree of diversity would indicate a good deal of disagreement. It would be nice to think that ethicists—or anyone else, for that matter—could come up with a recipe for preventing, or at least minimizing, these disagreements and thereby minimize the military invasions, terrorism, and various other violence caused by these disagreements. That may seem a bit optimistic, but it is worth thinking about how the study of ethics could move us closer to this goal. Extreme Tolerance and Intolerance We can start by identifying two positions on opposite ends of the spectrum: extreme tolerance and extreme intolerance. The extremely tolerant person will accept all cultures, perspectives, views, and ethical values expressed by any society, anywhere, and at any time. In short an extremely tolerant person tolerates everything. Extreme intolerance, on the other hand, involves tolerating nothing but one’s own view. Thus, the extremely intolerant culture Z rejects all other cultures from A through Y. One and only one position is acceptable to Z, and Z regards all other cultures as wrong. The extremely tolerant society, on the other hand, never considers another view to be wrong and never challenges or criticizes it. Thus, it would never need to engage another culture or society militarily. The extremely intolerant society may always be at war, however, for it always sees any culture with distinct views as being incorrect. It is likely that few, if any, cultures qualify as either extremely tolerant or extremely intolerant. Most fall between these two extremes. Considering the polar opposites is useful, however, mos81165_06_c06.indd 196 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.2 Alternatives to Traditional Theories of Ethics CHAPTER 6 because it gives us a sense of the limits involved in describing the various ways one might endorse, or advocate, tolerance. For even though many agree that “tolerance” is generally a good thing, we can see that too much tolerance could be as bad as too much intolerance. Imagine you are sitting quietly at home, watching a baseball game with a friend. Someone comes in, shoots your friend, and takes everything you own. An extremely tolerant person would have no objections to this scenario. More generally, extreme tolerance may lead to what one might call the paradox of tolerance, for the extremely tolerant person cannot object to the extremely intolerant person, and ends up tolerating the most vicious, dogmatic, and violent kind of intolerant behavior. Even if tolerance is a virtue, Aristotle would tell us that too much tolerance can be bad. However, a look around indicates that threats are more likely to stem from intolerance. A government may ban free speech or a particular religion. Two countries may go to war over a piece of land not because they each want it, but rather they each want to prevent the other from acquiring it. Terrorists may kill people who practice a different religion or those who simply hold different values. A town may practice informal discrimination against people regarded by the majority as “different,” whether because they are a different race, religion, sexual orientation, or have another minority identity. A person may decide that abortion is so immoral that it is acceptable to murder a doctor who performs abortions. Do philosophers, specifically ethicists, have tools to question these and other intolerant acts? Reflective Equilibrium In his extremely influential 1971 book A Theory of Justice, the philosopher John Rawls (1921–2002) puts forth a strategy he calls reflective equilibrium. While the full theory is quite complex, Rawls’s fundamental ideas help make clear our sense of fairness. Rawls believes any plausible conception of justice must be one that is regarded by all who participate in a society’s decisions as fair, and thus he is famous for characterizing justice as fairness (Rawls, 1971). Rawls describes a thought experiment where people come together to design a society in which they will at some point live. He puts a crucial condition on those designing this society: They are behind what he calls a “veil of ignorance” (1971). That is, they do not know what kind of person they will be in this future society: They do not know their gender, race, religion (if any), class, ethnicity, sexual orientation, physical handicaps, and so on. Thus, what the participants determine to be fair must express what each thinks would be fair for all. For instance, a man would not describe a society that discriminates against women, for he might discover that in this future society, he is one. Part of Rawls’s discussion requires the notion of reflective equilibrium, where individuals with various moral and political views discuss the moral and political views of others, in order to see what agreement can be reached. As Rawls describes the idea, “adopting the role of observing moral theorist, we investigate what principles people would acknowledge and accept the consequences of when they have an opportunity to consider other plausible conceptions and to assess their supporting grounds” (Rawls, 1971). To illustrate the idea further, consider the following example. John and Mary, who come from very different backgrounds, compare their notions of a just and fair society. They both are willing to consider the other’s viewpoint and recognize that some adjustment to their own notion may have to be made. Perhaps John is suspicious of religions other than his own, whereas Mary is an agnostic and thus has no religion. Through reflective equilibrium, John adjusts his beliefs to accept others who may not share his religious views, and Mary adjusts her beliefs to allow more tolerance for those who cherish their religious commitments. After much give and take, they mos81165_06_c06.indd 197 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics CHAPTER 6 come to a position they both accept. In a certain sense Rawls offers a sophisticated account of precisely what many people do all the time: compromise. In doing so he suggests a nonviolent way of solving our disputes, and thus provides us with another way to think about making our diverse and often contentious planet more harmonious. 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics W e have seen some of the best known ethical theories and some of the challenges they confront. We have also seen some of the alternatives to these traditional theories and some of their weaknesses. We will now look at more specific ethical issues, describe the problems they present, and examine how ethical theories might be used to resolve them. We will begin with personal or individual ethical issues before turning to more general social ethical issues, although there is often overlap between these. We will see that many ethical issues require us to think about the relationship between the individual and his or her society and how one influences the other. (See Table 6.2 for a list of topics to be explored in ethics.) Table 6.2: Concept review: Topics to be explored Individual issues in ethics Promises Free speech Greed Vegetarianism Euthanasia Social issues in ethics Animal rights Plato’s critique of democracy Rawls’s conception of fairness The environment The personal and the political Libertarianism Victimless crimes Promises We all make promises, and for the most part we expect promises to be kept. Since I expect others to keep their promises, deontological ethics insists that this means I should keep the promises I make. The utilitarian takes a different approach; perhaps there are situations in which the greatest number achieves the greatest net good by breaking a promise. We probably also think that promises have a certain context, or set of conditions. For example, we should not make promises we know we cannot keep. Yet it may not be unethical to make a promise, try our best to fulfill it, yet end up breaking it. Various kinds of examples bear out these ideas further. Imagine you promise to pay Smith $5 next week if he loans it to you today (you are friends, so he does not charge you interest). Smith may think that in addition to being paid back, if he loans you money, you might return the favor some day if he is in need. Similarly, you do not want Smith to mos81165_06_c06.indd 198 1/6/14 2:33 PM Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics CHAPTER 6 regard you as someone who does not meet his obligations; or perhaps you might need to borrow money again in the future, so you want to be sure to pay it back this time. One might look at this from the point of view of ethical egoism: You and Smith are both looking out for your self-interest, now and in the future. So Smith loans you the money, and you promise to pay it back (and do). On the one hand, your self-interest is best met by getting the money and ensuring the potential to borrow more. Smith’s self-interest is best met by loaning the money and ensuring his potential to borrow from you. The deontologist, on the other hand, says that you have made a promise to Smith—to pay him back—and that one should keep one’s promises; not out of selfinterest, but because it is the right thing to do. (We can determine that it is the right thing to do by looking at it from the perspective of the Golden Rule or from the perspective of Kant, who would suggest that morality requires that promises be kept.) Meanwhile, the utilitarian might say there are various outcomes, but paying back the loan will certainly create a utility calculation that would not be lower than any of the other outcomes. Presumably, being honest and keeping one’s promises are virtues—at least if done appropriately and in moderation—so the virtue ethicist will also insist that the money be paid back. As we see, then, the ethical egoist, the deontologist, the utilitarian, and the virtue ethicist all agree that the promise should be kept, but they arrive at that conclusion from very different directions. However, these theories may not always agree so nicely. Consider marriage vows, in which partners promise to love, cherish, honor, and obey, among other things, “till death do us part.” Despite the fact this promise is binding and often made before God, it is not always kept. Presumably, people make this promise fully intending to keep it, but circumstances change. Assuming one or both members of a marriage are sufficiently miserable to end it, the utilitarian would probably conclude that doing so would lead to the greatest good for the greatest number. The deontologist might say that although promises should never be made lightly, the Kantian “universality requirement”—that we act in such a way that it would always be the right thing to do in those circumstances—could be taken to mean that ending the marriage is the right thing to do. The virtue ethicist would probably argue that keeping a promise to remain married, if it makes one or both of those people miserable, is immoderate and fails to recognize that it is sometimes appropriate to break promises. In this case, however, one can also see that others might argue that a utility calculation, an application of the categorical imperative, or the virtue of honesty might require the marriage to continue. Thus, ethical theories might not only conflict with each other, but may even conflict with common sense. For instance, if one interprets Kant as saying that promises must never be broken, then it would violate his ethical principle to dissolve the marriage, even if it condemns both people to abject misery for the rest of their lives. This also shows that ethical theories are not really “recipes” that guarantee a certain and reliable ethical outcome. Instead, they can offer guidance for ascertaining right and wrong, so long as we understand that their application may change depending on a situation’s specifics. Free Speech In the United States specifically, a number of political and ethical questions arise from how one interprets the Constitution. It will be helpful to see a specific example of this from the Bill of Rights. The First Amendment to the Constitution of the United States reads: Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances. mos81165_06_c06.indd 199 1/6/14 2:33 PM CHAPTER 6 Section 6.3 Individual Issues in Ethics The questions this raises about religion—whether what is known is the “establishment” clause or the “free exercise” clause—are pretty well known. However, the questions of the freedom of speech and of the press raise issues that are also worth looking at, in terms of constitutionally protected rights, and what our ethical theories might say about when those rights might be violated. As we saw with the issue of promises, we probably start with an assumption that free speech, for individuals and for the media (or press), cannot be prohibited without a very good reason. In other words, free speech is always assumed to be protected unless legitimate reasons can be provided. Yelling “Fire!” The most famous example of when free speech can be prohibited comes from the Supreme Court case Schenck v. United States (1919), in which Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes noted that one should not be allowed to yell “Fire!” in a crowded theatre. The reason is that falsely indicating there is a fire could cause panic and put people in danger as they all rush toward the exits. Holmes’s reasoning sounds utilitarian: Even if the person yelling “Fire!” gets some degree of pleasure from doing so, everyone else is at risk of psychological trauma and physical injury. Thus, the greatest good for the greatest number demands prohibiting this kind of speech. The deontologist, who rejects lying on principle, would agree with Holmes’s conclusion, pointing out that falsely yelling “Fire!” is a lie. As we have seen before, two different ethical theories come to the same conclusion, though for different reasons. Even those who advocate the greatest amount of free speech recognize that in this specific case, the harm caused outweighs the right to say whatever one wishes. There are other such restrictions recognized in the law: One cannot threaten the life of the president, for example, nor freely joke about bombs or hijacking while in an airport. Most people recognize these as legitimate restrictions to the First Amendment’s guarantee of free speech. Freedom for Speech We Do Not Like Real life presents many situations in which one person’s right to say something may violate another person’s right not to hear (or see) it. For instance, there are various laws that regulate pornography’s production, distribution, and sale. Should adults be able to take whatever kind of pictures they want and sell them to another adult? Some argue that to prevent them from doing so is a restriction on free speech; others argue that pornography objectifies women (treating them solely as a means to an end, not as ends in themselves, in Kantian language) in ways that can lead to violence, sexual abuse, rape, and other i...
Purchase answer to see full attachment
User generated content is uploaded by users for the purposes of learning and should be used following Studypool's honor code & terms of service.

Explanation & Answer

Attached.

Utilitarianism and the Wage Gap
The gender-based wage gap that affects professional women in the United States is a
challenge that needs to be overcome in order to achieve true economic equality. Though it is
sometimes attempted to be explained away through some form of justification or another, like the
different career paths that are sought by men and women, the discrepancies in payment are still
prevalent (Thoreau, 2013). When all aspects are considered, this differentiation in remuneration is
meant to discriminate based only on gender presentation. In an alleged democracy, the possibility
of such discrimination occurring should be cause for concern. Though, often, these concerns are
purely of a material nature -- the equality of women depends on their financial independence, after
all -- they can also be examined from a purely ethical perspective. The problem of the wage gap is
more than just material or legal, but ethical in its core. With this in mind, it can be said that this
social landscape is unethical in its treatment of women, as it is detrimental to their personal and
professional development. Moreover, this can also have a negative impact on society as a whole.
Specifically, the ethical theory of utilitarianism can be used to examine the ethical dilemma that
the wage gap presents for society.
Theory Explanation
Consequentialism proposes the notion that moral values should guide actions towards a
particular unraveling, or consequence. It is based on these consequences, and the effects that they
have on the majority of a population, that an action can be judged as morally right or wrong. The
action, on its own, does not carry with it any moral or ethical expectations, but its results will
definitely have such an impact. If an action ends up producing a greater amount of good, then it
could be judged as being ethical. However, when the inverse occurs, the opposite judgement can
be made. Even when the same action occurs repeatedly, it can always be open to the possibility of

a different ethical judgement, depending on how each instance developed and the context in which
they developed. If it is expected that all actions ought to help towards the acquisition of a particular
moral value, then any action that, instead, serves as an obstacle to this purpose, would be
considered unethical.
Following this train of thought, utilitarianism proposes that the value that ought to be
chased is happiness. Though it might appear reductive, Mill describes the pursuit of happiness as
“the ultimate end… for the sake of which all other thin...


Anonymous
Goes above and beyond expectations!

Studypool
4.7
Trustpilot
4.5
Sitejabber
4.4

Related Tags